Skip to main content

2020 | OriginalPaper | Buchkapitel

Variables vs. Parameters in the Interpretation of Natural Language

verfasst von : Jan Köpping, Thomas Ede Zimmermann

Erschienen in: New Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence

Verlag: Springer International Publishing

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

This paper compares two systems of functional type logic that have been applied to the analysis of meaning composition in natural language: Montague’s Intensional Logic IL and its extensional substratum Ty2 of two-sorted type theory. The two systems differ in their treatment of reference and quantification over indices (like possible worlds or times): whereas the denotations of IL-formulae (inter alia) depend on indices as parameters, their Ty2-counterparts contain explicit free and bound variables for them. Building on earlier results, it is argued that, appearances to the contrary, the two systems are largely equivalent; that any differences in expressivity are irrelevant to said applications; and that the equivalence also extends to variations of the systems that make use of multiple indices (as in mixed systems of modal and temporal interpretation) or additional dimensions (as in standard accounts of context dependence).

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 390 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe




 

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Fußnoten
1
With the variability of the underlying Logical Space of possibilities, the intensions are generalizations of Kripke’s [17] possible worlds, as propagated in [19].
 
2
The \(\lambda \)-operator indicates functional abstraction: \([\lambda x. \dots \ x \ \dots ]\) is that function f that assigns \(\dots \ u \ \dots \) to any u in its domain D (which is left implicit); given the set-theoretic account of functions we thus have:
$$ [\lambda x. \dots \ x \ \dots ] \ = \ \{(u,v) \vert u \in D \ \& \ v = \dots \ u \dots \}.$$
 
3
Following [20], the sets \(\textit{Con}_{(s,b)}\) are usually referred to as \(\textit{Con}_b\), which we feel is confusing (given their interpretation) and moreover leads to complications when it comes to comparing IL and Ty2.
 
4
See [20, p. 387] and [9, p. 15] for other, less transparent ways of defining conjunction.
 
5
It ought to be mentioned that there is every reason to believe that Montague had been aware of Theorem (6), given the very design of IL.
 
6
In fact, it is almost that fragment, except for a little twist concerning constants occurring without index argument; cf. [30, p. 75].
 
7
Tautologies are among the obvious exceptions.
 
8
Hint: (7-a) and (8-a) boil down to a cardinality condition on \(D_s\); and the \(^*\)-counterpart of (8-b) is:
  • \((\lambda F^{((s,t),t)}. \ (\lambda \upsilon ^s_0. \ ( \lambda p^{(s,t)}. \ (p(\upsilon ^s_0) \ = F)))) \ (\lambda p. p(\upsilon ^s_0)).\)
 
9
The classic elimination algorithm from [4, p. 189] cannot be applied directly because it outputs terms of types outside \(\textit{IT}^+\). Thanks are due to Oleg Kiselyov for bringing up the question during the discussion following the LENLS presentation.
 
10
The syntactic variable t indicates the surface position from which the underlying noun plush toys has been moved and corresponds to the \(\lambda \)-bound Ty2-variable P in (13-b). See [10, p. 199f.] for an early formulation (and a different motivation) of such an analysis.
 
11
\(\chi '\), too, would have to be subjected to a meaning postulate in order to make sure it denotes a choice function \(\chi \), i.e. that \(w\in \chi (p)\) whenever \(p \ne \emptyset \).
 
12
The exact nature of the representation relation between contexts and indices varies across different versions of two-dimensional semantics and need not concern us here.
 
13
Cf. [15, p. 510], where the ban is presented as a descriptive observation on English and related languages. The more natural interpretation, following [18], takes it to be a defining criterion for context-dependence: unlike indices, contexts comprise those denotation-determining factors that cannot be shifted.
 
14
Here we slightly simplify matters: contexts are usually taken to contain more components than indices (cf. [14]); alternatively, they may be taken to be fully specified (utterance) situations (cf. [18]). In any case, these complications are orthogonal to our concerns.
 
15
The reasoning runs parallel to the proof Corollary (50b) in [16, Sec. 2.6]; see the next sub-section for this connection.
 
16
The (contextual) truth conditions of (23) are captured by equating index time \(t_0\) and context time \(t^*\) in (24), which still need to be kept apart to account for embedded occurrences of (23).
 
17
Apart from that a further result was proved to the effect that denotational equivalence holds across all types at diagonal points; obviously, this result is also covered by (27).
 
18
The ‘Y’ stands for ‘Yanovich’ on whose account [29] of backwards-looking operators (25) and (26) are based.
 
Literatur
1.
Zurück zum Zitat Bäuerle, R.: Pragmatisch-semantische Aspekte der NP-Interpretation. In: Faust, M., Harweg, R., Lehfeldt, W., Wienold, G. (eds.) Allgemeine Sprachwissenschaft, Sprachtypologie und Textlinguistik, pp. 121–131. Narr, Tübingen (1983) Bäuerle, R.: Pragmatisch-semantische Aspekte der NP-Interpretation. In: Faust, M., Harweg, R., Lehfeldt, W., Wienold, G. (eds.) Allgemeine Sprachwissenschaft, Sprachtypologie und Textlinguistik, pp. 121–131. Narr, Tübingen (1983)
2.
Zurück zum Zitat Carnap, R.: Meaning and Necessity. University of Chicago Press, Chicago (1947)MATH Carnap, R.: Meaning and Necessity. University of Chicago Press, Chicago (1947)MATH
4.
Zurück zum Zitat Curry, H.B., Feys, R.: Combinatory Logic, vol. I. North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam (1958)MATH Curry, H.B., Feys, R.: Combinatory Logic, vol. I. North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam (1958)MATH
6.
7.
Zurück zum Zitat Frege, G.: Über Sinn und Bedeutung. Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik NF 100(1), 25–50 (1892) Frege, G.: Über Sinn und Bedeutung. Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik NF 100(1), 25–50 (1892)
8.
Zurück zum Zitat Friedman, J., Warren, D.S.: \(\lambda \)-normal forms in an intensional logic for English. Studia Logica XXXIX(2–3), 311–324 (1980) Friedman, J., Warren, D.S.: \(\lambda \)-normal forms in an intensional logic for English. Studia Logica XXXIX(2–3), 311–324 (1980)
9.
Zurück zum Zitat Gallin, D.: Intensional and Higher-order Modal Logic. North-Holland Pub. Company, Amsterdam (1975)MATH Gallin, D.: Intensional and Higher-order Modal Logic. North-Holland Pub. Company, Amsterdam (1975)MATH
10.
Zurück zum Zitat Groenendijk, J., Stokhof, M.: Semantic analysis of WH-complements. Linguist. Philos. 5(2), 175–233 (1982)CrossRef Groenendijk, J., Stokhof, M.: Semantic analysis of WH-complements. Linguist. Philos. 5(2), 175–233 (1982)CrossRef
11.
Zurück zum Zitat Heim, I., Kratzer, A.: Semantics in Generative Grammar. Blackwell Publishers Ltd., Oxford (1998) Heim, I., Kratzer, A.: Semantics in Generative Grammar. Blackwell Publishers Ltd., Oxford (1998)
15.
Zurück zum Zitat Kaplan, D.: Demonstratives. An essay on the semantics, logic, metaphysics and epistemology of demonstratives and other indexicals. In: Almog, J., Perry, J., Wettstein, H. (eds.) Themes from Kaplan, pp. 481–563. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1989) Kaplan, D.: Demonstratives. An essay on the semantics, logic, metaphysics and epistemology of demonstratives and other indexicals. In: Almog, J., Perry, J., Wettstein, H. (eds.) Themes from Kaplan, pp. 481–563. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1989)
16.
Zurück zum Zitat Köpping, J., Zimmermann, T.E.: Looking backwards in type logic. Inquiry (forthcoming) Köpping, J., Zimmermann, T.E.: Looking backwards in type logic. Inquiry (forthcoming)
17.
Zurück zum Zitat Kripke, S.A.: Semantical considerations on modal logic. Acta Philosophica Fennica 16, 83–94 (1963)MathSciNetMATH Kripke, S.A.: Semantical considerations on modal logic. Acta Philosophica Fennica 16, 83–94 (1963)MathSciNetMATH
18.
Zurück zum Zitat Lewis, D.K.: Index, context, and content. In: Kanger, S., Öhman, S. (eds.) Philosophy and Grammar, pp. 79–100. Reidel, Dordrecht (1980)CrossRef Lewis, D.K.: Index, context, and content. In: Kanger, S., Öhman, S. (eds.) Philosophy and Grammar, pp. 79–100. Reidel, Dordrecht (1980)CrossRef
19.
Zurück zum Zitat Montague, R.: Pragmatics. In: Klibansky, R. (ed.) Contemporary Philosophy. Volume I: Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, pp. 102–122. La Nuova Italia Editrice, Florence (1968) Montague, R.: Pragmatics. In: Klibansky, R. (ed.) Contemporary Philosophy. Volume I: Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, pp. 102–122. La Nuova Italia Editrice, Florence (1968)
21.
Zurück zum Zitat Montague, R.: The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary English. In: Hintikka, J., Moravcsik, J., Suppes, P. (eds.) Approaches to Natural Language, pp. 221–242. Reidel, Dordrecht (1973)CrossRef Montague, R.: The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary English. In: Hintikka, J., Moravcsik, J., Suppes, P. (eds.) Approaches to Natural Language, pp. 221–242. Reidel, Dordrecht (1973)CrossRef
22.
Zurück zum Zitat Parsons, T.: Frege’s hierarchies of indirect senses and the paradox of analysis. In: French, P., Uehling, T., Wettstein, H. (eds.) Midwest Studies in Philosophy VI: The Foundations of Analytic Philosophy, pp. 37–57. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis (1981) Parsons, T.: Frege’s hierarchies of indirect senses and the paradox of analysis. In: French, P., Uehling, T., Wettstein, H. (eds.) Midwest Studies in Philosophy VI: The Foundations of Analytic Philosophy, pp. 37–57. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis (1981)
23.
Zurück zum Zitat Percus, O.: Constraints on some other variables in syntax. Nat. Lang. Semant. 9(1), 173–229 (2000)CrossRef Percus, O.: Constraints on some other variables in syntax. Nat. Lang. Semant. 9(1), 173–229 (2000)CrossRef
24.
Zurück zum Zitat Saarinen, E.: Backwards-looking operators in tense logic and in natural language. In: Hintikka, J., Niiniluoto, I., Saarinen, E. (eds.) Essays on Mathematical and Philosophical Logic, pp. 341–367. Reidel, Dordrecht (1979)CrossRef Saarinen, E.: Backwards-looking operators in tense logic and in natural language. In: Hintikka, J., Niiniluoto, I., Saarinen, E. (eds.) Essays on Mathematical and Philosophical Logic, pp. 341–367. Reidel, Dordrecht (1979)CrossRef
25.
Zurück zum Zitat Scott, D.: Advice on modal logic. In: Lambert, K. (ed.) Philosophical Problems in Logic, pp. 143–173. Reidel, Dordrecht (1970)CrossRef Scott, D.: Advice on modal logic. In: Lambert, K. (ed.) Philosophical Problems in Logic, pp. 143–173. Reidel, Dordrecht (1970)CrossRef
26.
Zurück zum Zitat Stalnaker, R.: A theory of conditionals. In: Rescher, N. (ed.) Studies in Logical Theory, pp. 41–55. Blackwell, Oxford (1968) Stalnaker, R.: A theory of conditionals. In: Rescher, N. (ed.) Studies in Logical Theory, pp. 41–55. Blackwell, Oxford (1968)
28.
Zurück zum Zitat Stalnaker, R.: The problem of logical omniscience, II. In: Context and Content, pp. 255–273. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1999) Stalnaker, R.: The problem of logical omniscience, II. In: Context and Content, pp. 255–273. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1999)
29.
Zurück zum Zitat Yanovich, I.: Expressive power of “now” and “then” operators. J. Log. Lang. Inf. 24(1), 65–93 (2015) MathSciNetCrossRef Yanovich, I.: Expressive power of “now” and “then” operators. J. Log. Lang. Inf. 24(1), 65–93 (2015) MathSciNetCrossRef
30.
31.
Zurück zum Zitat Zimmermann, T.E.: Fregean compositionality. In: Ball, D., Rabern, B. (eds.) The Science of Meaning, pp. 276–305. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2018) Zimmermann, T.E.: Fregean compositionality. In: Ball, D., Rabern, B. (eds.) The Science of Meaning, pp. 276–305. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2018)
32.
Zurück zum Zitat Zimmermann, T.E.: Representing intensionality: variables vs. parameters. In: Gutzmann, D., Matthewson, L., Meier, C., Rullmann, H., Zimmermann, T.E. (eds.) The Wiley Blackwell Companion to Semantics. Oxford, Wiley (forthcoming) Zimmermann, T.E.: Representing intensionality: variables vs. parameters. In: Gutzmann, D., Matthewson, L., Meier, C., Rullmann, H., Zimmermann, T.E. (eds.) The Wiley Blackwell Companion to Semantics. Oxford, Wiley (forthcoming)
Metadaten
Titel
Variables vs. Parameters in the Interpretation of Natural Language
verfasst von
Jan Köpping
Thomas Ede Zimmermann
Copyright-Jahr
2020
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-58790-1_11

Premium Partner