Skip to main content
Erschienen in: Theory and Decision 3-4/2019

04.01.2019

What are axiomatizations good for?

verfasst von: Itzhak Gilboa, Andrew Postlewaite, Larry Samuelson, David Schmeidler

Erschienen in: Theory and Decision | Ausgabe 3-4/2019

Einloggen

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

Do axiomatic derivations advance positive economics? If economists are interested in predicting how people behave, without a pretense to change individual decision making, how can they benefit from representation theorems, which are no more than equivalence results? We address these questions. We propose several ways in which representation results can be useful and discuss their implications for axiomatic decision theory.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Fußnoten
1
See Dekel and Lipman (2010) and Luce et al. (1990) for related discussions.
 
2
It is interesting to observe that both approaches date back to the 1950s at the latest (see, e.g., Luce and Suppes 1965 on stochastic choice), but that they recently seem to have moved to center stage after several decades in which they received less attention.
 
3
We refer to this type of justification as “meta-scientific” as it involves modeling of the work of scientists, as described in Sect. 2.2. above. It is not part of the work of the applied economist who attempts to explain or to shape economic reality; rather, it is part of the work of the philosopher or sociologist of science, who attempts to verify that the aforementioned economist does not use ill-defined terms and does not develop irrefutable, meaningless theories.
 
4
Specifically, we refer to Gilboa et al. (2009, 2012) who discuss the appeal of Savage’s axioms and the importance of the state space to which they are applied.
 
5
This is in line with our views of economic models as rhetorical devices (see Gilboa et al. 2014, 2106). Our focus here, however, is on the choice of modeling tools rather than on specific models.
 
6
Axiomatizations that are effective as rhetorical devices can also be thought of “framing effects”: a decision rule that may appear unreasonable in one representation may be more compelling in another.
 
7
As pointed out to us by Ivan Moscati, these and other leading economists varied in their motivation and in their views of expected utility as a normative and/or descriptive model of choice. We thank a referee for pointing out that economists at the time were apt to blur the distinction between normative and descriptive models. For example, Arrow (1951, p. 406) writes that, “In view of the general tradition of economics, which tends to regard rational behavior as a first approximation to actual, I feel justified in lumping the two classes of theory together.” One contribution of Kahneman and Tversky (1979) was to argue that descriptive models can be improved by not insisting they be normative.
 
8
Moscati (2018) describes early empirical investigations of the expected-utility axioms.
 
9
Among the best known violations of expected utility theory, preference reversals strike at the heart of the transitivity axiom. See Lichtenstein and Slovic (1971), Lindman (1971) and Grether and Plott (1979).
 
10
This is a real case that has not been analyzed by professional historians of science. It is based on the authors’ own impressions and personal histories.
 
11
We thank Peter Wakker for this and related observations.
 
12
Handa (1977) suggested the same formula where v was the identity.
 
13
This turned out to be a special case of Choquet expected utility theory (Schmeidler 1989).
 
14
Clearly, “convincing people” should be operationalized in a quantitative manner. Some people may be convinced to follow a decision model, while others may not; they may accept it for some applications but not for others, etc. Note that these measurement issues apply both to the term “normatively appealing” and to “objectively rational”.
 
15
Other concepts can be “qualitative probability”, “cost of temptation”, “similarity”, etc.
 
16
Famously, Savage also ridiculed his own defense by writing “I don’t mind being hanged as long as my reputation and good health are unharmed”. See Gilboa (2009) for further discussion of the delineation of applications in which state-dependent utility is unavoidable.
 
17
In the first, self-report has famously been used to measure well-being. Despite many problems with this measurement tool, “Subjective Well-Being” is still considered an important source of information. Likewise, in Aumann’s example involving the decision maker’s wife self-report would be a way to find out that the measured probability does not correspond to his beliefs.
 
18
See Moscati (2018) for a discussion of the development of utility theory.
 
19
See Cozic and Hill (2015) on axiomatizations as definitions of theoretical terms.
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Allais, M. (1952). Fondements d’une théorie positive des choix comportant un risque et critique des postulats et axiomes de l’École Américaine. Econométrie, 257–331. Allais, M. (1952). Fondements d’une théorie positive des choix comportant un risque et critique des postulats et axiomes de l’École Américaine. Econométrie, 257–331.
Zurück zum Zitat Allais, M. (1953). Le comportement de l’homme rationnel devant le risque: Citique des postulats et axiomes de l’École Américaine. Econometrica, 21(4), 503–56.CrossRef Allais, M. (1953). Le comportement de l’homme rationnel devant le risque: Citique des postulats et axiomes de l’École Américaine. Econometrica, 21(4), 503–56.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Anscombe, F. J., & Aumann, R. J. (1963). A definition of subjective probability. The Annals of Mathematics and Statistics, 34, 199–205.CrossRef Anscombe, F. J., & Aumann, R. J. (1963). A definition of subjective probability. The Annals of Mathematics and Statistics, 34, 199–205.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Arrow, K. J. (1951). Alternative approaches to the theory of choice in risk-taking situations. Econometrica, 19, 404–437.CrossRef Arrow, K. J. (1951). Alternative approaches to the theory of choice in risk-taking situations. Econometrica, 19, 404–437.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Carnap, R. (1923). Uber die Aufgabe der Physik und die Andwednung des Grundsatze der Einfachstheit. Kant-Studien, 28, 90–107.CrossRef Carnap, R. (1923). Uber die Aufgabe der Physik und die Andwednung des Grundsatze der Einfachstheit. Kant-Studien, 28, 90–107.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Cozic, M., & Hill, B. (2015). Representation theorems and the semantics of decision-theoretic concepts. Journal of Economic Methodology, 22, 292–311.CrossRef Cozic, M., & Hill, B. (2015). Representation theorems and the semantics of decision-theoretic concepts. Journal of Economic Methodology, 22, 292–311.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Debreu, G. (1954). Representation of a preference ordering by a numerical function. In R. M. Thrall, C. H. Coombs, & R. L. Davis (Eds.), Decision processes (pp. 159–165). New York: Wiley. Debreu, G. (1954). Representation of a preference ordering by a numerical function. In R. M. Thrall, C. H. Coombs, & R. L. Davis (Eds.), Decision processes (pp. 159–165). New York: Wiley.
Zurück zum Zitat de Finetti, F. (1931). Sul significato Soggettivo della Probabilità. Fundamenta Mathematicae, 17, 298–329.CrossRef de Finetti, F. (1931). Sul significato Soggettivo della Probabilità. Fundamenta Mathematicae, 17, 298–329.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat de Finetti, F. (1937). La prevision: ses lois logiques, ses sources subjectives. Annales de l’Institut Henri Poincare, 7, 1–68. de Finetti, F. (1937). La prevision: ses lois logiques, ses sources subjectives. Annales de l’Institut Henri Poincare, 7, 1–68.
Zurück zum Zitat Dekel, E., & Lipman, B. L. (2010). How (not) to do decision theory. Annual Review of Economics, 2, 257–282.CrossRef Dekel, E., & Lipman, B. L. (2010). How (not) to do decision theory. Annual Review of Economics, 2, 257–282.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Edwards, W. (1954). The theory of decision-making. Psychological Bulletin, 51, 380–417.CrossRef Edwards, W. (1954). The theory of decision-making. Psychological Bulletin, 51, 380–417.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Ellsberg, D. (1961). Risk, ambiguity and the savage axioms. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 75, 643–669.CrossRef Ellsberg, D. (1961). Risk, ambiguity and the savage axioms. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 75, 643–669.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Fishburn, P. C. (1978). On Handa’s new theory of cardinal utility and the maximization of expected return. Journal of Political Economy, 86, 321–324.CrossRef Fishburn, P. C. (1978). On Handa’s new theory of cardinal utility and the maximization of expected return. Journal of Political Economy, 86, 321–324.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Gilboa, I. (2009). A theory of decision under uncertainty. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Gilboa, I. (2009). A theory of decision under uncertainty. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Gilboa, I., Postlewaite, A., & Schmeidler, D. (2009). Is it always rational to satisfy savage’s axioms? Economics and Philosophy, 25, 285–296.CrossRef Gilboa, I., Postlewaite, A., & Schmeidler, D. (2009). Is it always rational to satisfy savage’s axioms? Economics and Philosophy, 25, 285–296.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Gilboa, I., Postlewaite, A., & Schmeidler, D. (2012). Rationality of belief. Synthese, 187, 11–31.CrossRef Gilboa, I., Postlewaite, A., & Schmeidler, D. (2012). Rationality of belief. Synthese, 187, 11–31.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Gilboa, I., Postlewaite, A., Samuelson, L., & Schmeidler, D. (2014). Economic models as analogies. Economic Journal, 128, F513–F533.CrossRef Gilboa, I., Postlewaite, A., Samuelson, L., & Schmeidler, D. (2014). Economic models as analogies. Economic Journal, 128, F513–F533.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Gilboa, I., Postlewaite, A., Samuelson, L., & Schmeidler, D. (2016). Economics: Between prediction and criticism. International Economic Review (2016) (forthcoming) Gilboa, I., Postlewaite, A., Samuelson, L., & Schmeidler, D. (2016). Economics: Between prediction and criticism. International Economic Review (2016) (forthcoming)
Zurück zum Zitat Gilboa, I., & Schmeidler, D. (2001). A theory of case-based decisions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Gilboa, I., & Schmeidler, D. (2001). A theory of case-based decisions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Grether, D. M., & Plott, C. R. (1979). Economic theory of choice and the preference reversal phenomenon. American Economic Review, 69, 623–638. Grether, D. M., & Plott, C. R. (1979). Economic theory of choice and the preference reversal phenomenon. American Economic Review, 69, 623–638.
Zurück zum Zitat Habermas, J. (1981). Theory of communicative action, Vol I: Reason and the rationalization of society, English edition (p. 1984). Boston: Beacon. Habermas, J. (1981). Theory of communicative action, Vol I: Reason and the rationalization of society, English edition (p. 1984). Boston: Beacon.
Zurück zum Zitat Handa, J. (1977). Risk, probabilities, and a new theory of cardinal utility. Journal of Political Economy, 85, 97–122.CrossRef Handa, J. (1977). Risk, probabilities, and a new theory of cardinal utility. Journal of Political Economy, 85, 97–122.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Herstein, I. N., & Milnor, J. (1953). An axiomatic approach to measurable utility. Econometrica, 21, 291–297.CrossRef Herstein, I. N., & Milnor, J. (1953). An axiomatic approach to measurable utility. Econometrica, 21, 291–297.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Jaffray, J.-Y. (1975). Existence of a continuous utility function: An elementary proof. Econometrica, 43, 981–983.CrossRef Jaffray, J.-Y. (1975). Existence of a continuous utility function: An elementary proof. Econometrica, 43, 981–983.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Jensen, N.-E. (1967). An introduction to Bernoullian utility theory I, II. Sedish Journal of Economics, 69(163–183), 229–247. Jensen, N.-E. (1967). An introduction to Bernoullian utility theory I, II. Sedish Journal of Economics, 69(163–183), 229–247.
Zurück zum Zitat Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, 47, 263–291.CrossRef Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, 47, 263–291.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Karni, E. (1996). Probabilities and beliefs. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 13, 249–262.CrossRef Karni, E. (1996). Probabilities and beliefs. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 13, 249–262.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Lichtenstein, S., & Slovic, P. (1971). Reversals of preferences between bids and choices in gambling decisions. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 89, 46–55.CrossRef Lichtenstein, S., & Slovic, P. (1971). Reversals of preferences between bids and choices in gambling decisions. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 89, 46–55.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Lindman, H. R. (1971). Inconsistent preferences among gambles. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 89, 390–397.CrossRef Lindman, H. R. (1971). Inconsistent preferences among gambles. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 89, 390–397.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Loewenstein, G. (1992). The fall and rise of psychological explanation in the economics of intertemporal choice. In G. Loewenstein & J. Elster (Eds.), Choice over time (pp. 3–34). New York: Russell Sage. Loewenstein, G. (1992). The fall and rise of psychological explanation in the economics of intertemporal choice. In G. Loewenstein & J. Elster (Eds.), Choice over time (pp. 3–34). New York: Russell Sage.
Zurück zum Zitat Luce, R. D., Krantz, D., Suppes, P., & Tversky, A. (1990). Foundations of measurement, Vol. III: Representation, axiomiatization, and invariance. New York: Academic Press. Luce, R. D., Krantz, D., Suppes, P., & Tversky, A. (1990). Foundations of measurement, Vol. III: Representation, axiomiatization, and invariance. New York: Academic Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Luce, R. D., & Suppes, P. (1965). Preference, utility and subjective probability. In R. D. Luce, R. R. Bush, & E. Galanter (Eds.), Handbook of mathematical psychology (Vol. III, pp. 249–410). New York: Wiley. Luce, R. D., & Suppes, P. (1965). Preference, utility and subjective probability. In R. D. Luce, R. R. Bush, & E. Galanter (Eds.), Handbook of mathematical psychology (Vol. III, pp. 249–410). New York: Wiley.
Zurück zum Zitat Marschak, J. (1950). Rational behavior, uncertain prospects, and measurable utility. Econometrica, 18, 111–141.CrossRef Marschak, J. (1950). Rational behavior, uncertain prospects, and measurable utility. Econometrica, 18, 111–141.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Marshall, A. (1920). Principles of economics (8th ed.). London: Macmillan. Marshall, A. (1920). Principles of economics (8th ed.). London: Macmillan.
Zurück zum Zitat Moscati, I. (2016). How economists came to accept expected utility theory: The case of Samuelson and Savage. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 30, 219–236.CrossRef Moscati, I. (2016). How economists came to accept expected utility theory: The case of Samuelson and Savage. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 30, 219–236.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Moscati, I. (2018). Measuring utility: From the marginal revolution to behavioral economics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Moscati, I. (2018). Measuring utility: From the marginal revolution to behavioral economics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Popper, K. R. (1934). Logik der Forschunghe: The logic of scientific discovery (English Edition 1958). London: Hutchinson and Co. Popper, K. R. (1934). Logik der Forschunghe: The logic of scientific discovery (English Edition 1958). London: Hutchinson and Co.
Zurück zum Zitat Quiggin, J. (1982). A theory of anticipated utility. Journal of Economic Behaviorand Organization, 3, 225–243.CrossRef Quiggin, J. (1982). A theory of anticipated utility. Journal of Economic Behaviorand Organization, 3, 225–243.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Ramsey, F. P. (1926). Truth and probability. In R. Braithwaite (Ed.), The foundation of mathematics and other logical essays (p. 1931). London: Routledge. Ramsey, F. P. (1926). Truth and probability. In R. Braithwaite (Ed.), The foundation of mathematics and other logical essays (p. 1931). London: Routledge.
Zurück zum Zitat Savage, L. J. (1954). New York: The foundations of statistics. Oxford: Wiley. Savage, L. J. (1954). New York: The foundations of statistics. Oxford: Wiley.
Zurück zum Zitat Schmeidler, D. (1989). Subjective probability and expected utility without additivity. Econometrica, 57, 571–587.CrossRef Schmeidler, D. (1989). Subjective probability and expected utility without additivity. Econometrica, 57, 571–587.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Sen, A. (1993). Internal consistency of choice. Econometrica, 61, 495–521.CrossRef Sen, A. (1993). Internal consistency of choice. Econometrica, 61, 495–521.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Simon, H. (1957). Models of man. New York: Wiley. Simon, H. (1957). Models of man. New York: Wiley.
Zurück zum Zitat Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1992). Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5, 297–323.CrossRef Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1992). Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5, 297–323.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat von Neumann, J., & Morgenstern, O. (1944). Theory of games and economic behavior. Princeton: Princeton University Press. von Neumann, J., & Morgenstern, O. (1944). Theory of games and economic behavior. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Yaari, M. (1987). The dual theory of choice under risk. Econometrica, 55, 95–115.CrossRef Yaari, M. (1987). The dual theory of choice under risk. Econometrica, 55, 95–115.CrossRef
Metadaten
Titel
What are axiomatizations good for?
verfasst von
Itzhak Gilboa
Andrew Postlewaite
Larry Samuelson
David Schmeidler
Publikationsdatum
04.01.2019
Verlag
Springer US
Erschienen in
Theory and Decision / Ausgabe 3-4/2019
Print ISSN: 0040-5833
Elektronische ISSN: 1573-7187
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-018-09685-1

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 3-4/2019

Theory and Decision 3-4/2019 Zur Ausgabe