Skip to main content
Erschienen in: Argumentation 1/2022

13.07.2021 | Original Research

Adversariality in Argumentation: Shortcomings of Minimal Adversariality and A Possible Reconstruction

verfasst von: Iñaki Xavier Larrauri Pertierra

Erschienen in: Argumentation | Ausgabe 1/2022

Einloggen

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

Minimal adversariality consists in the opposition of contradictory conclusions in argumentation, and its usual metaphorical expression as a game between combating arguers has seen it be criticized from a number of perspectives: the language used, whether cooperation best attains the argumentative telos of epistemic betterment, and the ideal nature of the metaphor itself. This paper explores primarily the idealization of deductive argumentation, which is problematic due to its attenuated applicability to a dialectic involving premises and justificatory biases that are left hidden and unelucidated. To clarify the issue and offer up a solution, we consider minimal adversariality as an involuntary state of affairs before relating this interpretation to a link between rational persuasion and the attainment of epistemic betterment. Through this we see how the idealizing tendencies of minimal adversariality can be reduced even in argumentation involving premises whose justifications for any arguer are inaccessible to any other arguer.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Fußnoten
1
This essay differentiates argument as constituting the set of premises that justify a conclusion, portrayed here as AB, from argumentation as the practice of arguers critically engaging with each other’s arguments, portrayed here as “AB”.
 
2
Casey (2020, p. 97) makes this distinction as well. This is obviously an idealization, as argumentation can also turn irrational. We discuss irrationality in argument when introducing the notion of adversariality in Sect. 2.
 
3
The way that “conclusion” is being used in this essay is not as a justified singular proposition that closes a deductive argument, but as any proposition that has been logically treated, either being proven or not via deductive justification, which can then be appropriated to extend already ongoing argumentation.
 
4
Govier, for example, considers ‘good or sufficient grounds’ as what informs an argument’s cogency (1999, p. 46).
 
5
This reflects a need for a holistic modelling of our notion of argumentation that considers both epistemic and psychosocial features. This need may be realized in a more eclectic psychological account of argumentation. See, for example, Kidd (2016, p. 397) and Hornikx and Hahn (2012).
 
6
The issue of how disagreement plays a role in argumentation is outlined in Sect. 2.
 
7
See, Govier (1999, p. 245; 2010, p. 2); van Eemeren and Grootendorst (2004, pp. 61–62); Rooney (2010, p. 211); Hundleby (2013, p. 247); Novaes (2016, p. 2618).
 
8
To clarify, when used throughout this paper, “→” means differently than either → or (→), in that the latter two express the logical entailment relation per se while the former expresses the relation being deployed in argumentative process. See also, Note 1.
 
9
Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for pressing me on this point.
 
10
See, Gregg and Mahadevan (2014, p. 10); Aikin (2011, p. 250).
 
11
See, Moulton (1983, p. 153), Rooney (2010, p. 211), and Stevens and Cohen (2019, p. 5). Aikin (2011) has argued that, at times, adversarial stances can serve epistemic ends. Nevertheless, it should be noted that whatever epistemic ends are instantiated by such adversariality are incidental to the non-epistemic dynamic of one’s adversarial attitude, and thus should not be counted as part of this attitude’s general character.
 
12
(3) can turn dangerous when one arguer is willing to stand by the truth of their position even with no regard for the moral good. See Gilbert (1997, p. 43) for a discussion.
 
13
An anonymous reviewer has pertinently noted that behavioral intolerance in argumentation, such as through intimidation, typically does not function to elicit conceptual change in an arguer, for instead what we usually get is some kind of performative acquiescence if not outright opposition. However, my inclusion of ancillary adversariality as persuasive is not to gloss over the fact that such adversarial framing is often not persuasive at all, but simply that it can be persuasive in the irrational sense of behavioral maneuvers eliciting conceptual change. It is solely in this irrational capacity that an ancillarily adversarial agent is persuasive. Furthermore, yes, irrational persuasion is not within the sole jurisdiction of ancillary adversariality—one can be persuaded irrationally even without outright conflict—so something more than the avoidance of conflict in argumentation is needed to secure rational persuasion. This is precisely part of the theme addressed in Sect. 3 where I criticize a particular construal of minimal adversariality that realizes irrational persuasion.
 
14
In this case, we are assuming that the law of the excluded middle is operative and that “¬XY” is not being argued for. The argument form where ¬Y is the conclusion could be represented as, “A¬Y”, where A = (A1 ʌ A2 ʌ … An) and A is not necessarily ¬X.
 
15
See, for example, van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1984, pp. 85–88). The idea of disagreement as integral to the entire process of argumentation is also not an uncommon view. See, Jackson and Jacobs (1980); Willard (1989); Gilbert (1996).
 
16
Notice that this dynamic of giving and asking for clear and valid reasons between Prover and Skeptic is an argumentative norm similar to that of Brandom (1994).
 
17
Novaes (2016, p. 2619) also makes this point.
 
18
Alternatively, the norm of cooperation may end up playing too much of a role in one’s theory of argumentation if the function of disagreement is given too much of a back seat. This may be a way of interpreting Steven and Cohen’s (2019) critique of Bailin and Battersby (2016).
 
19
For the sake of argument, I am assuming that logical entailment is necessarily truth preserving, but I recognize the ostensibly interminable argument between entailment’s truth as applicable to all possible worlds or just this one, or whether that truth is analytically or synthetically derived. It is outside the scope of this paper to enter this debate.
 
20
This analysis mirrors that of John Searle (1995, p. 24).
 
21
Of course, one could argue that other inferential rules could better conclude Y from X, but we are foreclosing on the importance of this for now since we are dealing with deductive argumentation here.
 
22
See, Burrow (2010, p. 236). Adversariality in games wherein you have contrasting winners and losers may even be less relevant in games that have the participants either winning or losing together—i.e., participants are playing the game itself instead of each other. Indeed, game examples of the latter variety would be more apt to describe argumentation by. (Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for bringing this up.) However, we may augment the relevancy of adversariality in argumentation in the sense that, while I may come to legitimately know a position contrary to mine via truth-preserving justification, I may not necessarily know that I know this fact. This implies that I could be considered a loser in the way of not acknowledging my own epistemic gain. Nonetheless, pursuing this line of thought is not for this paper.
 
23
See, Rooney (2010, pp. 221–222); Hundleby (2013, p. 240). Indeed, Govier describes participants in argument as ‘opponents’ (1999, p. 244).
 
24
Philosophical discourse in particular has been chastised for its legacy of ancillary argumentation (Rooney 2010, p. 227).
 
25
Stevens and Cohen (2019) offer up similar remarks (p. 19n31). This distinction between telos and motivation resembles one made in Walton and Krabbe (1995, p. 66) between dialogue purpose and participant goals. Having non-epistemic motivations may also be why, according to Gilbert, ancillary adversariality in argumentation can be ‘exhilarating and downright enjoyable to those to whom it is considered play’ (Gilbert 1994, p. 102).
 
26
The metaphor, as ideal, assumes that ‘whatever we need to know about arguers’ motivations, assumptions, knowledge, reasoning, and feelings’ are encapsulated by the arguers’ spoken and/or written words (Hample 2007, p. 166). See also Mills (2005) for a general discussion on idealizing tendencies within philosophical theory-crafting.
 
27
Rooney even considers that the justificatory force between premises and their conclusion is at least partly conditioned by the argument’s hidden assumptions/premises (2012, p. 324).
 
28
See Kidd (2016, § 5) for a list of empirical accounts describing how social experience capacitates biases within one’s rational capacities. Moreover, this natural propensity towards identity prejudice features in broadly motivationalist understandings of argumentative virtue, such as one mirrored in Annas (2011).
 
29
See Warren (1988) for a discussion on how adversarial notions of argumentation are especially costly for the argumentative participation and perceived validity of minority speakers.
 
30
See, Le Dœuff (1989, p. 12). It is this capacity of minimal adversariality’s game metaphorization, as naïve acceptance of majority narratives informing doxastic attitudes towards what are the appropriate premises to have in argument, that is being criticized here. The easy solution would be to adopt an open-mindedness in argumentation about the premises being brought to the table, perhaps realizable in a back-and-forth process between the arguers that is sensitive to the premises intended to support an argument. However, following our interpretation of adversariality as an involuntary state of affairs in the relation between argumentation’s telos of epistemic betterment and rational persuasion, there are implicit rational limitations to this open-mindedness in terms of how a proposition’s truth value can be argued for or falsified, which is the primary theme addressed in Sect. 4.
 
31
See also, Casey (2020, p. 83).
 
32
One popular way, as noted by Stevens and Cohen, is to view adversarial competition, even in ancillary modes, as mitigating in this regard (2019, pp. 8, 19n32). What is evoked is a more general model of Darwinian natural selection, wherein our best arguments are born out of a battle for survival of the fittest due to the human capacity for argumentation being an evolutionary adaptation, a stance held by Mercier and Sperber (2017). This strictly evolutionary perspective however, as an adequate explanation on the causation and function of argumentation, is contested by Novaes (2013; 2018), who instead situates argumentation as a more socially conditioned phenomenon than a biologically adapted one.
 
33
See Hundleby (2013, pp. 253–254) for a related example.
 
34
Regardless, even if the resolution of contradiction is rationally made via further instances of deductive argumentation, this neither speaks for nor against such resolution being a necessary condition for argumentation. This is because the telos of argumentation – epistemic betterment as progressive attainment towards the truth – can obtain whether seemingly contradictory truths are reached or not. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for the clarificatory request.
 
35
This resembles the argument made in Nagel (1974).
 
36
I recognize that there is uncertainty relating to the exact meaning of propositional referentiality. However, all I am arguing for is the minimal stance that it is at least merely possible that propositions about experiences can be justified by reference to those very experiences, which I do not think is a terribly controversial stance to take at all.
 
37
This may correspond to Novaes’ understanding of Mercier and Sperber’s distinction between an objective reason—‘a fact that objectively supports some conclusion’—and a psychological reason—‘a mental representation of an objective reason’ (Novaes 2018, p. 514n3). Notwithstanding, we are not identifying the involuntariness of logical entailment with that of experiential justification: the former impinges upon people equally while the latter does not. Nonetheless, insofar as experiential justification impinges involuntarily at all, then it attains features of minimal adversariality. It is not required for experiential justification to attain the character of rational justification that logical entailment has for my argument to work, hence their merely analogous relation.
 
38
I am here trying to avoid having as a criticizing remark to my argument the applicability of the statement, “you exist as a woman in terms of a phenomenological association, but you do not exist as a woman in terms of a biological assignment”, which is not a contradictory statement to make.
 
39
This shows that there is a way to read adversariality into the conclusions of an argumentation without having to rescue it, as Casey (2020) does, through the involuntariness of belief change through persuasion.
 
40
I am thus not advocating here for a form of dialogical foundationalism, in which the truth of privileged premises needs to be taken for granted without any justificatory reasoning attached to it. See Rhode (2017) for a pertinent discussion. Relatedly, what I am not saying here is that one can rationally use experience to involuntarily justify any proposition whatsoever to have it attain a privileged status, for there are legitimate issues pertaining to subject-matter considerations about propositions whose truth value one may try to adjudicate on. For instance, it is patently absurd that one can experientially justify, without defeat, whether the earth is round or flat, because the proposition of earth-roundness, as it is typically understood, is not solely under experiential purview. Matters like gender dysphoria, or phenomenological construals of gender and gender expression more generally, however typically are. Now, exactly how a proposition’s subject matter becomes typically constructed—e.g., whether purely experiential or not—is not made concrete from the outset, in that what constitutes its set of proper defeaters can itself be fleshed out via argumentation. Still, once a statement’s subject matter is defined as under experiential jurisdiction, whether wholly or partly, it is in its capacity as experientially informed that the statement becomes inevitably subject to no defeat outside that jurisdiction of the one employing that statement in argumentation.
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Aikin, S. 2011. In Defense of War and Sport Metaphors in Argument. Philos Rhetoric 44 (3): 250–272.CrossRef Aikin, S. 2011. In Defense of War and Sport Metaphors in Argument. Philos Rhetoric 44 (3): 250–272.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Annas, J. 2011. Intelligent Virtue. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Annas, J. 2011. Intelligent Virtue. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bailin, S., Battersby, M. 2016. DAMed If You Do; DAMed If You Don’t: Cohen’s “Missed Opportunities”. In: Bondy P, Benacquista L (eds), Argumentation, Objectivity and Bias. 11th International Conference of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation, University of Windsor, Windsor, 18–21 May 2016. Bailin, S., Battersby, M. 2016. DAMed If You Do; DAMed If You Don’t: Cohen’s “Missed Opportunities”. In: Bondy P, Benacquista L (eds), Argumentation, Objectivity and Bias. 11th International Conference of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation, University of Windsor, Windsor, 18–21 May 2016.
Zurück zum Zitat Bondy, P. 2010. Argumentative injustice. Informal Log 30 (3): 263–278. Bondy, P. 2010. Argumentative injustice. Informal Log 30 (3): 263–278.
Zurück zum Zitat Brandom, R. 1994. Making it explicit: Reasoning, representing, and discursive commitment. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Brandom, R. 1994. Making it explicit: Reasoning, representing, and discursive commitment. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Burrow, S. 2010. Verbal sparring and apologetic points: Politeness in gendered argumentation contexts. Informal Log 30 (3): 235–262. Burrow, S. 2010. Verbal sparring and apologetic points: Politeness in gendered argumentation contexts. Informal Log 30 (3): 235–262.
Zurück zum Zitat Casey, J. 2020. Adversariality and argumentation. Informal Log 40 (1): 77–108.CrossRef Casey, J. 2020. Adversariality and argumentation. Informal Log 40 (1): 77–108.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Cohen, D.H. 1995. Argument is War … and War is Hell: Philosophy, Education, and Metaphors for Argumentation. Informal Log 17 (2): 177–188. Cohen, D.H. 1995. Argument is War … and War is Hell: Philosophy, Education, and Metaphors for Argumentation. Informal Log 17 (2): 177–188.
Zurück zum Zitat Cohen, D.H. 2013a. Commentary on: Katharina von Radziewsky’s “The virtuous arguer: One person, four characters”. In: Mohammed D, Lewiński M (eds), Virtues of Argumentation. 10th International Conference of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation, University of Windsor, Windsor, 22–25 May 2013. Cohen, D.H. 2013a. Commentary on: Katharina von Radziewsky’s “The virtuous arguer: One person, four characters”. In: Mohammed D, Lewiński M (eds), Virtues of Argumentation. 10th International Conference of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation, University of Windsor, Windsor, 22–25 May 2013.
Zurück zum Zitat Fricker, M. 2007. Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRef Fricker, M. 2007. Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Gilbert, M.A. 1994. Feminism, argumentation and coalescence. Informal Log 16 (2): 95–113. Gilbert, M.A. 1994. Feminism, argumentation and coalescence. Informal Log 16 (2): 95–113.
Zurück zum Zitat Gilbert, M.A. 1996. How to win an argument, 2nd ed. New York: Wiley. Gilbert, M.A. 1996. How to win an argument, 2nd ed. New York: Wiley.
Zurück zum Zitat Gilbert, M.A. 1997. Coalescent Argumentation. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Gilbert, M.A. 1997. Coalescent Argumentation. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Zurück zum Zitat Gilbert, M.A. 2014. Arguing with People. Peterborough: Broadview Press. Gilbert, M.A. 2014. Arguing with People. Peterborough: Broadview Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Govier, T. 1999. The Philosophy of Argument. Newport News: Vale Press. Govier, T. 1999. The Philosophy of Argument. Newport News: Vale Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Govier, T. 2010. A practical study of argument, 7th ed. Belmont: Wadsworth. Govier, T. 2010. A practical study of argument, 7th ed. Belmont: Wadsworth.
Zurück zum Zitat Gregg, A.P., and N. Mahadevan. 2014. Intellectual arrogance and intellectual humility: An evolutionary-epistemological account. Journal of Psychology and Theology 42 (1): 7–18.CrossRef Gregg, A.P., and N. Mahadevan. 2014. Intellectual arrogance and intellectual humility: An evolutionary-epistemological account. Journal of Psychology and Theology 42 (1): 7–18.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Hornikx, J., and U. Hahn. 2012. Reasoning and argumentation: Towards an integrated psychology of argumentation. Think Reasoning 18 (3): 225–243.CrossRef Hornikx, J., and U. Hahn. 2012. Reasoning and argumentation: Towards an integrated psychology of argumentation. Think Reasoning 18 (3): 225–243.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Hundleby, C. 2013. Aggression, politeness, and abstract adversaries. Informal Log 33 (2): 238–262.CrossRef Hundleby, C. 2013. Aggression, politeness, and abstract adversaries. Informal Log 33 (2): 238–262.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Jackson, S., and S. Jacobs. 1980. Structure of conversational argument: Pragmatic bases for the enthymeme. The Quarterly Journal of Speech 66 (3): 251–265.CrossRef Jackson, S., and S. Jacobs. 1980. Structure of conversational argument: Pragmatic bases for the enthymeme. The Quarterly Journal of Speech 66 (3): 251–265.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Johnson, R.H. 2000. Manifest Rationality: A Pragmatic Theory of Argument. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Johnson, R.H. 2000. Manifest Rationality: A Pragmatic Theory of Argument. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Zurück zum Zitat Kidd, I.J. 2016. Intellectual humility, confidence, and argumentation. Topoi 35 (2): 395–402.CrossRef Kidd, I.J. 2016. Intellectual humility, confidence, and argumentation. Topoi 35 (2): 395–402.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Lakoff, G., and M. Johnson. 1980. Metaphors We Live By. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Lakoff, G., and M. Johnson. 1980. Metaphors We Live By. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Le Dœuff, M. 1989. The Philosophical Imaginary (trans: Gordon C). Stanford: Stanford University Press. Le Dœuff, M. 1989. The Philosophical Imaginary (trans: Gordon C). Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Mattice, S.A. 2014. Metaphor and Metaphilosophy: Philosophy as Combat, Play, and Aesthetic Experience. London: Lexington Books. Mattice, S.A. 2014. Metaphor and Metaphilosophy: Philosophy as Combat, Play, and Aesthetic Experience. London: Lexington Books.
Zurück zum Zitat Mercier, H., and D. Sperber. 2011. Why do humans reason? Arguments for an argumentative theory. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 34 (2): 57–74.CrossRef Mercier, H., and D. Sperber. 2011. Why do humans reason? Arguments for an argumentative theory. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 34 (2): 57–74.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Mercier, H., and D. Sperber. 2017. The Enigma of Reason. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.CrossRef Mercier, H., and D. Sperber. 2017. The Enigma of Reason. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Mills, C.W. 2005. “Ideal Theory” as Ideology. Hypatia 20 (3): 165–184. Mills, C.W. 2005. “Ideal Theory” as Ideology. Hypatia 20 (3): 165–184.
Zurück zum Zitat Moulton, J. 1983. A Paradigm of Philosophy: The Adversary Method. In Discovering Reality: Feminist Perspectives on Epistemology, Metaphysics, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science, ed. S. Harding and M.B. Hintikka, 149–164. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Moulton, J. 1983. A Paradigm of Philosophy: The Adversary Method. In Discovering Reality: Feminist Perspectives on Epistemology, Metaphysics, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science, ed. S. Harding and M.B. Hintikka, 149–164. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Zurück zum Zitat Nagel, T. 1974. What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review 83 (4): 435–450.CrossRef Nagel, T. 1974. What is it like to be a bat? Philosophical Review 83 (4): 435–450.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Novaes, C.D. 2013. A dialogical account of deductive reasoning as a case study for how culture shapes cognition. J Cognit Cult 13 (5): 459–482.CrossRef Novaes, C.D. 2013. A dialogical account of deductive reasoning as a case study for how culture shapes cognition. J Cognit Cult 13 (5): 459–482.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Novaes, C.D. 2016. Reductio ad absurdum from a dialogical perspective. Philosophical Studies 173 (10): 2605–2628.CrossRef Novaes, C.D. 2016. Reductio ad absurdum from a dialogical perspective. Philosophical Studies 173 (10): 2605–2628.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Novaes, C.D. 2018. The enduring enigma of reason. Mind & Language 33 (5): 513–524.CrossRef Novaes, C.D. 2018. The enduring enigma of reason. Mind & Language 33 (5): 513–524.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Rhode, C. 2017. The burden of proof in philosophical persuasion. Argumentation 31 (3): 535–554.CrossRef Rhode, C. 2017. The burden of proof in philosophical persuasion. Argumentation 31 (3): 535–554.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Rooney, P. 2010. Philosophy, adversarial argumentation, and embattled reason. Informal Log 30 (3): 203–234. Rooney, P. 2010. Philosophy, adversarial argumentation, and embattled reason. Informal Log 30 (3): 203–234.
Zurück zum Zitat Rooney, P. 2012. When philosophical argumentation Impedes social and political progress. Journal of Social Philosophy 43 (3): 317–333.CrossRef Rooney, P. 2012. When philosophical argumentation Impedes social and political progress. Journal of Social Philosophy 43 (3): 317–333.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Searle, J. 1995. The Construction of Social Reality. New York: The Free Press. Searle, J. 1995. The Construction of Social Reality. New York: The Free Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Stevens, K., and D. Cohen. 2019. The attraction of the ideal has no traction on the real: On adversariality and roles in argument. Argum Advocacy 55 (1): 1–23. Stevens, K., and D. Cohen. 2019. The attraction of the ideal has no traction on the real: On adversariality and roles in argument. Argum Advocacy 55 (1): 1–23.
Zurück zum Zitat van Eemeren, F.H., and R. Grootendorst. 1984. Speech Acts in Argumentative Discussions: A Theoretical Model for the Analysis of Discussions Directed towards Solving Conflicts of Opinion. Dordrecht: Floris Publications.CrossRef van Eemeren, F.H., and R. Grootendorst. 1984. Speech Acts in Argumentative Discussions: A Theoretical Model for the Analysis of Discussions Directed towards Solving Conflicts of Opinion. Dordrecht: Floris Publications.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat van Eemeren, F.H., and R. Grootendorst. 2004. A Systematic Theory of Argumentation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. van Eemeren, F.H., and R. Grootendorst. 2004. A Systematic Theory of Argumentation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Walton, D.N. 1998. The New Dialectic: Conversational Contexts of Argument. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRef Walton, D.N. 1998. The New Dialectic: Conversational Contexts of Argument. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Walton, D.N., and E.C.W. Krabbe. 1995. Commitment in Dialogue: Basic Concepts of Interpersonal Reasoning. Albany: SUNY Press. Walton, D.N., and E.C.W. Krabbe. 1995. Commitment in Dialogue: Basic Concepts of Interpersonal Reasoning. Albany: SUNY Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Warren, K. 1988. Critical thinking and feminism. Informal Log 10 (1): 31–44. Warren, K. 1988. Critical thinking and feminism. Informal Log 10 (1): 31–44.
Zurück zum Zitat Willard, C.A. 1989. A theory of argumentation. Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press. Willard, C.A. 1989. A theory of argumentation. Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press.
Metadaten
Titel
Adversariality in Argumentation: Shortcomings of Minimal Adversariality and A Possible Reconstruction
verfasst von
Iñaki Xavier Larrauri Pertierra
Publikationsdatum
13.07.2021
Verlag
Springer Netherlands
Erschienen in
Argumentation / Ausgabe 1/2022
Print ISSN: 0920-427X
Elektronische ISSN: 1572-8374
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-021-09553-3

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 1/2022

Argumentation 1/2022 Zur Ausgabe

Premium Partner