Skip to main content
Erschienen in: Journal of Automated Reasoning 8/2021

Open Access 09.09.2021

Handling Transitive Relations in First-Order Automated Reasoning

verfasst von: Koen Claessen, Ann Lillieström

Erschienen in: Journal of Automated Reasoning | Ausgabe 8/2021

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

We present a number of alternative ways of handling transitive binary relations that commonly occur in first-order problems, in particular equivalence relations, total orders, and transitive relations in general. We show how such relations can be discovered syntactically in an input theory, and how they can be expressed in alternative ways. We experimentally evaluate different such ways on problems from the TPTP, using resolution-based reasoning tools as well as instance-based tools. Our conclusions are that (1) it is beneficial to consider different treatments of binary relations as a user, and that (2) reasoning tools could benefit from using a preprocessor or even built-in support for certain types of binary relations.
Hinweise

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

1 Introduction

This paper explores different possible ways of speeding up the handling of commonly occurring kinds of transitive binary relations, in the context of general first-order automated reasoning.
As an example, consider the following set of first-order axioms for a relation symbol \(R\):
A possible goal we may want to prove is:
A quick investigation of the first three axioms reveals that \(R\) is an equivalence relation, which is a binary relation that occurs quite commonly in practice in first-order problems. In this paper, we suggest that an alternative way of dealing with equivalence relations is not to axiomatize them (as we did in the example), but to choose a new function symbol \(rep\), and replace all occurrences of \(R\;({ x },{ y })\) with the literal \(rep\;({ x }){=}rep\;({ y })\). Doing so makes the problem simpler, because the three axioms for equivalence relations (reflexivity, symmetry, and transitivity) can be removed. The resulting (complete) set of axioms is:
The goal we need to prove becomes:
As our experimental results show, this alternative way of dealing with equivalence relations presented here is beneficial for some theorem provers, because it is easier for those provers to reason about equality and an extra function symbol than about a binary predicate symbol wth additional axioms.
This paper identifies six kinds of commonly occurring binary relations (that all happen to be transitive) for which alternative treatments are proposed, that are designed to be simpler to reason about than their standard axiomatizations. The kinds of binary relations dealt with in this paper are:
  • Equivalence relations, and partial equivalence relations,
  • Total orders, and strict total orders,
  • (general) transitive relations, with and without reflexivity.
It can be very beneficial to hardcode special ways of dealing of commonly occurring functions or relations in automated reasoning tools, as demonstrated by for example equality handling, AC handling, and arithmetic operators and relations, which have native support in many reasoning tools. However, we chose to investigate alternative ways of expressing the mentioned binary relations directly in the input problem, rather than new methods that need to be built-in to theorem provers, for several reasons: (1) it is cheaper than implementing built-in methods, simply because no extra implementation effort is required, (2) it is more flexible, because one is not tied to one particular theorem prover, and (3) it is beneficial to the user of the tool (who can choose what alternative to use) as well as the implementer of the tool (who can implement automatic transformations that choose the alternative). Such automatic transformations are also described in the paper.
The target audience for this paper is thus both people who use reasoning tools and people who implement reasoning tools.
Related Work Binary relations, and transitive relations and transitive closure in particular, have been given special treatment in automated reasoning tools in a variety of different domains. For example, Kodkod [12] and CVC4 [8] reason about relational logic for finite domains, where even transitive closure can be supported. Cristiá et al. [3] present a decision procedure for sets, relations, and partial functions that is complete for finite sets. Horrocks and Gough propose an efficient way of dealing with transitive binary relations in the context of description logics [6]. Schmidt and Hustadt present a method that translates problems in propositional modal logic with background theories (that can also include transitivity) into first-order logic [9].
For general first-order logic, chaining [1] is a family of built-in methods that limit the use of transitivity-like axioms in proofs by only allowing certain chains of them to occur in proofs. The result is a complete proof system that avoids the derivation of unnecessary consequences of transitivity. Chaining has been implemented inside one of the reasoning tools we considered for this paper (SPASS [13]). Also more specific binary relations that the ones considered in this paper have been implemented in this way [5].
In contrast, this paper presents purely preprocessing techniques for speeding up reasoning about different kinds of transitive binary relations occurring in general first-order logic. As far as we know, this is also the first paper to consider methods for dealing with (partial) equivalence relations and (strict) total orders specifically.

2 Common Properties of Binary Relations

In this section, we take a look at commonly occurring properties of binary relations, which combinations of these are interesting for us to treat specially, and how we may go about discovering these. Note that the logic that we use throughout the paper is unsorted first-order logic with equality.
Take a look at Fig. 1. It lists 8 basic and common properties of binary relations. Each of these properties can be expressed using one logic clause, which makes it easy to syntactically identify the presence of such a property in a given theory1.
When we investigated the number of occurrences of these basic properties in a subset of the TPTP problem library (v7.0.0)2 [11], we ended up with the table in Fig. 2. The table was constructed by gathering all clauses from all TPTP problems (after clausification), and keeping every clause that only contained one binary relation symbol, no function symbols, and, possibly, equality. Each such clause was then syntactically categorized as an expression of a basic property of a binary relation symbol. The total number of such clauses found is indicated in the table for each basic property. We found 163 clauses that did not fit any of the 8 properties we chose as basic properties, but were instead instances of two new properties. Both of these were quite esoteric and did not seem to have a standard name in mathematics.
The table also contains occurrences where a negated relation was stated to have a certain property, and also occurrences where a flipped relation (a relation with its arguments swapped) was stated to have a certain property, and also occurrences of combined negated and flipped relations. This explains for example why the number of occurrences of total relations is the same as for asymmetric relations; if a relation is total, the negated relation is asymmetric and vice-versa.
We adopt the following notation. Given a relation \(R\), the negated version of \(R\), denoted \(R^{\lnot {}}\), is defined as follows:
The flipped version of \(R\), denoted https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10817-021-09605-z/MediaObjects/10817_2021_9605_IEq10_HTML.gif , is defined as follows:
We lift these two notions to properties of relations as follows. Given a property of binary relations \({ prop }\), we introduce its negated version, which is denoted by \({ prop }^{\lnot {}}\). The property \({ prop }^{\lnot {}}\) holds for \(R\) if and only if \({ prop }\) holds for \(R^{\lnot {}}\):
Similarly, we introduce the flipped version of a property \({ prop }\), which is denoted by https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10817-021-09605-z/MediaObjects/10817_2021_9605_IEq18_HTML.gif . The property https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10817-021-09605-z/MediaObjects/10817_2021_9605_IEq19_HTML.gif holds for \(R\) if and only if \({ prop }\) holds for https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10817-021-09605-z/MediaObjects/10817_2021_9605_IEq22_HTML.gif :
Using this notation, we can for example say that \({ total }\) is equivalent with \({ asymmetric }^{\lnot {}}\). Sometimes the property we call \({ euclidean }\) here is called \({ right }\;{ euclidean }\); the corresponding variant \({ left }\;{ euclidean }\) can be denoted https://static-content.springer.com/image/art%3A10.1007%2Fs10817-021-09605-z/MediaObjects/10817_2021_9605_IEq28_HTML.gif . Note that \({ prop }^{\lnot {}}\) is not the same as \(\lnot {}{ prop }\)! For example, a relation \(R\) can be \({ reflexive }\), or \({ reflexive }^{\lnot {}}\) (which means that \(\lnot {}R\) is reflexive), or \(\lnot {}{ reflexive }\), which means that \(R\) is not reflexive.
Using this notation on the 8 original basic properties from Fig. 1, we end up with 32 new basic properties that we can use. (However, as we have already seen, some of these are equivalent to others.)
This paper will look at 6 kinds of different binary relations, which are defined as combinations of basic properties:
As a side note, in mathematics, strict total orders are sometimes defined using a property called trichotomous, which means that exactly one of \(R\;({ x },{ y })\), \({ x }{=}{ y }\), or \(R\;({ y },{ x })\) must be true. However, when this property is clausified in the presence of transitivity, one ends up with \({ antisymmetric }^{\lnot {}}\) which says that at least one of \(R\;({ x },{ y })\), \({ x }{=}{ y }\), or \(R\;({ y },{ x })\) must be true. There seems to be no standard name in mathematics for the property \({ antisymmetric }^{\lnot {}}\), which is why we use this name.
In Fig. 3, we display the number of binary relations we have found in (our subset of) the TPTP for each category. The next section describes how we found these.

3 Syntactic Discovery of Common Binary Relations

Our goal is to automatically choose the right treatment of equivalence relations, total orders, and general transitive relations. Thus, we must have an automatic way of identifying these relations in a given theory. It is relatively easy to discover for example an equivalence relation in a theory by means of syntactic inspection. If we find the presence of the axioms \({ reflexive }\), \({ symmetric }\), and \({ transitive }\), for the same relational symbol \(R\), we know that \(R\) is an equivalence relation.
But, there are many other ways of axiomatizing equivalence relations. For example, a much more common way to axiomatize equivalence relations in the TPTP is to state the two properties \({ reflexive }\) and \({ euclidean }\) for \(R\).
Rather than enumerating all possible ways to axiomatize certain relations by hand, we wrote a program that computes all possible ways for any combination of basic properties to imply any other combination of basic properties. Our program generates a table that can be precomputed in a minute or so and then used to very quickly detect any alternative axiomatization of binary relations using basic properties.
Let us explain how this table was generated. We start with a list of 32 basic properties (the 8 original basic properties, plus their negated, flipped, and negated flipped versions). Firstly, we use an automated theorem prover (we used E [10]) to discover which of these are equivalent with other such properties. The result is displayed in Fig. 4. Thus, 17 basic properties can be removed from the list, because they can be expressed using other properties. The list of basic properties now has 15 elements left.
Secondly, we want to generate all implications of the form \(\{ { prop }_1,{..},{ prop }_n\}\Rightarrow { prop }\) where the set \(\{ { prop }_1,{..},{ prop }_n\}\) is minimal. We do this separately for each \({ prop }\). The results are displayed in Fig. 5.
The procedure uses a simple constraint solver (a SAT-solver) to keep track of all implications it has tried so far, and consists of one main loop. At every loop iteration, the constraint solver guesses a set \(\{ { prop }_1,{..},{ prop }_n\}\) from the set of all properties \(P{-}\{ { prop }\}\). The procedure then asks E whether or not \(\{ { prop }_1,{..},{ prop }_n\}\Rightarrow { prop }\) is valid. If it is, then we look at the proof that E produces, and print the implication \(\{ { prop }_a,{..},{ prop }_b\}\Rightarrow { prop }\), where \(\{ { prop }_a,{..},{ prop }_b\}\) is the subset of properties that were used in the proof. We then also tell the constraint solver never to guess a superset of \(\{ { prop }_a,{..},{ prop }_b\}\) again. If the guessed implication can not be proven, we tell the constraint solver to never guess a subset of \(\{ { prop }_1,{..},{ prop }_n\}\) again. The procedure stops when no guesses that satisfy all constraints can be made anymore.
After the loop terminates, we remove all implications that are subsumed by others.
In order to avoid generating inconsistent sets \(\{ { prop }_1,{..},{ prop }_n\}\) (that would imply any other property), we also add the artificial inconsistent property \({ false }\) to the set, and generate implications for this property first. We exclude any found implication here from the implication sets of the real properties.
This procedure generates a complete list of minimal implications. It works well in practice, especially if all guesses made by the SAT-solver are maximized according to their size. The vast majority of the time is spent on the implication proofs, and no significant time is spent in the SAT-solver.
To detect a binary relation \(R\) with certain properties in a given theory, we simply gather all basic properties about \(R\) that occur in the theory, and then compute which other properties they imply, using the pre-generated table.
Also, certain properties can be derived for a binary relation \(R_2\) if \(R_2\) is implied by another binary relation \(R_1\), and \(R_1\) has that property. This holds for reflexivity, totality and seriality. Similarly, if \(R_2\) is antisymmetric or coreflexive, the same property can be derived for \(R_1\). When having derived a new property of a relation in this way, we iterate the procedure of finding implied properties using the precomputed table until no new information is gained. In this way, we never perform full theorem proving, but we nonetheless detect many binary relations with the listed basic properties.
In the following three sections, we describe how to deal with equivalence relations, total orders, and general transitive relations, respectively.

4 Handling Equivalence Relations

Equalification As mentioned in the introduction, an alternative way of handling equivalence relations \(R\) is to create a new symbol \(rep\) and replace all occurrences of \(R\) with a formula involving \(rep\):
To explain the above notation: We have two theories, one on the left-hand side of the arrow, and one on the right-hand side of the arrow. The proposed transformation transforms any theory that looks like the left-hand side into a theory that looks like the right-hand side. We write \({ T }\;[ {..}{ e }{..}]\) for theories in which \({ e }\) occurs syntactically; in the transformation, all occurrences of \({ e }\) should be replaced.
We call the above transformation equalification. This transformation may be beneficial because reasoning about the equivalence relation now involves built-in equality reasoning instead of reasoning about an unknown symbol using axioms.
The transformation is correct, meaning that it preserves (non-)satisfiability:
Theorem 1
(Correctness of equalification) Two theories \({ H }\) and \({ H' }\) that respectively match the LHS and RHS of equalification, are equisatisfiable.
Proof
(\(\Rightarrow \)) Assume we have \(m\models { H }\), then \(m\;(R)\)3 is an equivalence relation. Let the interpretation \({ m' }\) interpret all existing symbols as \(m\) does. Moreover, let \({ m' }\;(rep)\) be a representative function of the equivalence relation \(m\;(R)\). This means that we have \({ m' }\models (R\;({ x },{ y })\Leftrightarrow rep\;({ x })\,{=}\,rep\;({ y }))\), which means that \({ m' }\) is a model of \({ H' }\).
(\(\Leftarrow \)) Assume we have \({ m' }\models { H' }\). Let the interpretation \(m\) interpret all existing symbols as \({ m' }\) does. Moreover, let \(({ x },{ y })\in {}m\;(R)\) precisely when \({ m' }\;(rep) ({ x }){=}{ m' } \;(rep) ({ y })\). The relation \(m\;(R)\) is clearly reflexive, symmetric, and transitive, and therefore we have \(m\models { H }\). \(\square \)
In the transformation, we also remove the axioms for reflexivity, symmetry, and transitivity, because they are not needed anymore. But what if \(R\) is axiomatized as an equivalence relation using different axioms? Then we can remove any axiom about \(R\) that is implied by reflexivity, symmetry, and transitivity. Luckily we have already computed a table of which properties imply which other ones (shown in Fig. 5).
Pequalification There are commonly occurring binary relations called partial equivalence relations that almost behave as equivalence relations, but not quite. In particular, they do not have to obey the axiom of reflexivity. Can we do something for these too?
A set with a partial equivalence relation \(R\) can be partitioned into two subsets: (1) one subset on which \(R\) is an actual equivalence relation, and (2) one subset of elements which are not related to anything, not even themselves.
Thus, an alternative way of handling partial equivalence relations \(R\) is to create two new symbols, \(rep\) and \(P\), and replace all occurrences of \(R\) with a formula involving \(rep\) and \(P\):
Here, \(P\) is the predicate that indicates the subset on which \(R\) behaves as an equivalence relation.
We call this transformation pequalification. This transformation may be beneficial because the reasoning now involves built-in equality reasoning instead of reasoning about an unknown symbol using axioms. However, there is also a clear price to pay since the size of the problem grows considerably.
The transformation is correct, meaning that it preserves (non-)satisfiability:
Theorem 2
(Correctness of pequalification) Two theories \({ H }\) and \({ H' }\) that respectively match the LHS and RHS of pequalification, are equisatisfiable.
Proof
(\(\Rightarrow \)) Assume we have \(m\models { H }\), then \(m\;(R)\) is a partial equivalence relation. Let the interpretation \({ m' }\) interpret all existing symbols as \(m\) does. Moreover, let \({ m' }\;(P)\) be the set of domain elements \({ x }\) for which we have \(({ x },{ x })\in {}m\;(R)\), i.e. the subset of the domain where \(R\) is an actual equivalence relation. Let \({ m' }\;(rep)\) be a representative function of the partial equivalence relation \(m\;(R)\). This means that we have \({ m' }\models (R\;({ x },{ y })\Leftrightarrow (P\;({ x })\,{\wedge }\,P \;({ y })\,{\wedge }\,rep \;({ x }) = rep \;({ y })))\), which means that \({ m' }\) is a model of \({ H' }\).
(\(\Leftarrow \)) Assume we have \({ m' }\models { H' }\). Let the interpretation \(m\) interpret all existing symbols as \({ m' }\) does. Moreover, let \(({ x },{ y })\in {}m\;(R)\) precisely when \({ m' }\;(P) ({ x })\,{\wedge }\,{ m' } \;(P) ({ y })\,{\wedge }\,{ m' } \;(rep) ({ x }){=}{ m' } \;(rep) ({ y })\). The relation \(m \;(R)\) is clearly symmetric and transitive, and therefore we have \(m\models { H }\). \(\square \)
Intuitively, one can see that this transformation is correct by realising that the elements on which the relation \(R\) is not reflexive cannot be related to any other elements. This is because \(R \;({ x },{ y })\) together with symmetry and transitivity gives us \(R\;({ x },{ x })\). Thus, when we encounter \(R\;({ x },{ y })\) in the LHS theory, we know that both \({ x }\) and \({ y }\) are in the set defined by \(P\). (This holds also when \({ x }\) equals \({ y }\)). Since \(R\) is an equivalence relation on this set, we can use the transformation of pure equivalence relations on the subset \(P\) to get \(P\;({ x }){\wedge }P \;({ y })\Rightarrow rep\;({ x })\,{=}\,rep \;({ y })\).

5 Handling Total Orders

Ordification Many reasoning tools have built-in support for arithmetic, in particular they support an order \(\leqslant \) on numbers. It turns out that we can “borrow” this operator when handling general total orders. Suppose we have a total order:
We now introduce a new injective function:
We then replace all occurrences of \(R\) with a formula involving \(rep\) in the following way:
(Here, \(\leqslant \) is the order on reals.) We call this transformation ordification. This transformation may be beneficial because the reasoning now involves built-in arithmetic reasoning instead of reasoning about an unknown symbol using axioms.
The above transformation is correct, meaning that it preserves (non-)satisfiability:
Theorem 3
(Correctness of ordification) Two theories \({ H }\) and \({ H' }\) that respectively match the LHS and RHS of ordification, are equisatisfiable.
Proof
(\(\Rightarrow \)) If we have \(m\models { H }\), then without loss of generality (by Löwenheim-Skolem), we can assume that the domain of \(m\) is countable. Also, \(m\;(R)\) is a total order. Let the interpretation \({ m' }\) interpret all existing symbols as \(m\) does. We now construct \({ m' }\;(rep)\) recursively as a mapping from the model domain to \({\mathbb {R}}\), such that we have \(({ x },{ y })\in {}m\;(R)\) precisely when \({ m' }\;(rep)\;({ x })\leqslant { m' }\;(rep)\;({ y })\), in the following way. Let \(\{ { a }_0,{ a }_1,{ a }_2,{..}\}\) be the domain of the model, and set \({ m' }\;(rep)\;({ a }_0)\,{:=}\,\mathrm {0}\). For any \({ n }{>}\mathrm {0}\), pick a value for \({ m' }\;(rep)\;({ a }_n)\) that is consistent with the total order \(R\) and all earlier domain elements \({ a }_i\), for \(\mathrm {0}\leqslant { i }{<}{ n }\). This can always be done because there is always extra room for a new, unique element between any two distinct values of \({\mathbb {R}}\). Thus \({ m' }\;(rep)\) is injective and we also have a model \({ m' }\) of \({ H' }\).
(\(\Leftarrow \)) Assume we have \({ m' }\models { H' }\). Let the interpretation \(m\) interpret all existing symbols as \({ m' }\) does. Moreover, let \(({ x },{ y })\in {}m\;(R)\) precisely when \({ m' }\;(rep)\;({ x })\leqslant { m' }\;(rep)\;({ y })\). It is clear that \(m\;(R)\) is total and transitive, and also antisymmetric because \({ m' }\;(rep)\) is injective, and therefore \(m\models { H }\). \(\square \)
Note on \({\mathbb {Q}}\) vs. \({\mathbb {R}}\) The proof would have worked for \({\mathbb {Q}}\) as well instead of \({\mathbb {R}}\). The transformation can therefore be used for any tool that supports \({\mathbb {Q}}\) or \({\mathbb {R}}\) or both, and should choose whichever comparison operator is cheapest if there is a choice. Using integer arithmetic would however not have been correct.
Note on injectivity The transformation requires an axiom that expresses that \(rep\) is injective. There are two natural ways in which this can be expressed. Here is a direct axiom:
And here is an axiom that makes use of a helper function \(rep^{-1}\) which plays the role of \(rep\)s inverse:
These two are logically equivalent.
Note on strict total orders One may have expected to have a transformation specifically targeted to strict total orders, i.e. something like:
However, the transformation for total orders already covers this case! Any strict total order \(R\) is also recognized as a total order \(R^{\lnot {}}\), and ordification already transforms such theories in the correct way. The only difference is that \(R\;({ x },{ y })\) is replaced with \(\lnot {}(rep\;({ x })\leqslant rep\;({ y }))\) instead of \(rep\;({ x }){<}rep\;({ y })\), which is satisfiability-equivalent. (We found no performance difference in practice between these choices.)
Maxification Some reasoning tools do not have orders on real arithmetic built-in, but they may have other concepts that are built-in that can be used to express total orders instead. One such concept is handling of associative, commutative (AC) operators.
For such a tool, one alternative way of handling total orders \(R\) is to create a new function symbol \(max\) and replace all occurrences of \(R\) with a formula involving \(max\):
We call this transformation maxification. This transformation may be beneficial because the reasoning now involves built-in equality reasoning with AC unification (and one extra axiom) instead of reasoning about an unknown relational symbol (using three axioms).
The above transformation is correct, meaning that it preserves (non-)satisfiability:
Theorem 4
(Correctness of maxification) Two theories \({ H }\) and \({ H' }\) that respectively match the LHS and RHS of maxification, are equisatisfiable.
Proof
(\(\Rightarrow \)) If we have \(m\models { H }\), then \(m\;(R)\) must be a total order. Let the interpretation \({ m' }\) interpret all existing symbols as \(m\) does. Let \({ m' }\;(max)\) be the maximum function associated with the total order \(m\;(R)\). The function \({ m' }\;(max)\) is associative and commutative, and we have that \({ m' }\;(max) ({ x },{ y }){=}{ x }\vee {}{ m' } \;(max) ({ x },{ y }){=}{ y }\). Moreover, we have \({ m' } \models R\;({ x },{ y })\Leftrightarrow max\;({ x },{ y }){=}{ y }\). Thus we also have a model \({ m' }\) of \({ H' }\).
(\(\Leftarrow \)) Assume we have \({ m' }\models { H' }\). Let the interpretation \(m\) interpret all existing symbols as \({ m' }\) does. Moreover, let \(({ x },{ y })\in {}m\;(R)\) precisely when \({ m' }\;(max) ({ x },{ y }){=}{ y }\). Now, \(m\;(R)\) is total (because of \({ m' }\;(max) ({ x },{ y }){=}{ x }\vee {}{ m' } \;(max) ({ x },{ y }){=}{ y }\)), antisymmetric (because of commutativity of \({ m' }\;(max)\)), and transitive (because of associativity of \({ m' }\;(max)\)), and therefore \(m\models { H }\). \(\square \)

6 Handling Transitive Relations in General

The treatments introduced so far all make use of built-in concepts of the reasoning tool, and they can be applied only to special cases of transitive relations. In this section we propose a more general approach, in which theories with a transitivity axiom are transformed into theories without that transitivity axiom. To this end, transitivity is specialized at each positive occurrence of the relational symbol. Such transformations may be beneficial because reasoning about transitivity in a naive way can be very expensive for theorem provers, because from transitivity there are many possible conclusions to draw that trigger each other “recursively”.
The transformations presented in this subsection only work on problems where every occurrence of \(R\) is either positive or negative (and not both, such as under an equivalence operator). If this is not the case, the problem has to be translated into one where this is the case. This can for example be done by means of clausification.
Detransification A general way of handling any transitive relation \(R\) is to create a new symbol \(Q\) and replace all positive occurrences of \(R\) with a formula involving \(Q\) (see below, positive occurrences are denoted by \({+}R\)); the negative occurrences are simply replaced by \(\lnot {}Q\):
We call this transformation detransification. It can be applied to any theory that involves a transitivity axiom. The transformation removes the transitivity, but adds for every positive occurrence of \(R\;({ x },{ y })\) an implication that says “for any \({ r }\), if you could reach \({ x }\) from \({ r }\), now you can reach \({ y }\) too”. Thus, we have specialized the transitivity axiom for every positive occurrence of \(R\).
Note that in the RHS theory, \(Q\) does not have to be transitive! Nonetheless, the transformation is correct, meaning that it preserves (non-)satisfiability:
Theorem 5
(Correctness of detransification) Two theories \({ H }\) and \({ H' }\) that respectively match the LHS and RHS of detransification, are equisatisfiable.
Proof
(\(\Rightarrow \)) If we have \(m\models { H }\), then \(m\;(R)\) is transitive. Let the interpretation \({ m' }\) interpret all existing symbols as \(m\) does. Moreover, let \({ m' }\;(Q) ({ x },{ y }){:=}m\;(R)({ x },{ y })\). We have to show that \({ m' }\;(R)({ x },{ y })\) implies \({ m' }\;(Q)({ x },{ y })\), which is trivial, and that \({ m' }\;(R)({ x },{ y })\) implies \(\forall {}\;{ r }.\;{ m' }\;(Q)({ r },{ x })\Rightarrow { m' }\;(Q)({ r },{ y })\), which is indeed the case because \({ m' }\;(R)\) is transitive. Thus we have \({ m' }\models { H' }\).
(\(\Leftarrow \)) Assume we have \({ m' }\models { H' }\). Let the interpretation \(m\) interpret all existing symbols as \({ m' }\) does. Moreover, let \(({ x },{ y })\in {}m\;(R)\) precisely when \({ m' }\;(Q)({ x },{ y }){\wedge }\forall {}\;{ r }.\;{ m' }\;(Q)({ r },{ x })\Rightarrow { m' }\;(Q)({ r },{ y })\). We have to show that \(\lnot {}m\;(Q)({ x },{ y })\) implies \(\lnot {}m\;(R)({ x },{ y })\), which is the same as showing that \(m\;(Q)({ x },{ y }){\wedge }\forall {}\;{ r }.\;m\;(Q)({ r },{ x })\Rightarrow m\;(Q)({ r },{ y })\) implies \(m\;(Q)({ x },{ y })\). \(m\;(R)\) is also transitive (by transitivity of implication). Thus we also have \(m\models { H }\). \(\square \)
Detransification can be seen as performing one resolution step with each positive occurrence of the relation and the transitivity axiom. A positive occurrence R(ab) of a transitive relation \(R\), resolved with the transitivity axiom \( R\;({ x },{ y }){ \& }R\;({ y },{ z })\Rightarrow R\;({ x },{ z })\) becomes \(R\;({ x },{ a })\Rightarrow R\;({ x },{ b })\) under the substitution y := a, z := b.
Detransification with reflexivity Detransification can be simplified for transitive relations that are also reflexive. In particular, we can simplify the formula with which we replace positive occurrences of the relation symbol \(R\):
We now replace any positive occurrence of \(R\;({ x },{ y })\) with an implication that says “for any \({ r }\), if you could reach \({ x }\) from \({ r }\), now you can reach \({ y }\) too”. Thus, we have specialized the transitivity axiom for every positive occurrence of \(R\). The part that we omit here (namely \(Q\;({ x },{ y })\)) is implicitly implied by the fact that \(R\) is reflexive.
Similarly to the detransification transformation above, \(Q\) does not have to be transitive in the RHS theory. Nonetheless, the transformation is correct, meaning that it preserves (non-)satisfiability:
Theorem 6
(Correctness of detransification with reflexivity) Two theories \({ H }\) and \({ H' }\) that respectively match the LHS and RHS of detransification with reflexivity, are equisatisfiable.
Proof
(\(\Rightarrow \)) If we have \(m\models { H }\), then \(m\;(R)\) is reflexive and transitive. Let the interpretation \({ m' }\) interpret all existing symbols as \(m\) does. Moreover, let \(({ x },{ y })\in {}{ m' }\;(Q)\) precisely when \(m\;(R)({ x },{ y })\). \({ m' }\;(Q)\) is obviously reflexive. We have to show that \({ m' }\;(R)({ x },{ y })\) implies \(\forall {}\;{ r }.\;{ m' }\;(Q)({ r },{ x })\Rightarrow { m' }\;(Q)({ r },{ y })\), which is indeed the case because \({ m' }\;(R)\) is transitive. Thus we have \({ m' }\models { H' }\).
(\(\Leftarrow \)) Assume we have \({ m' }\models { H' }\), then \({ m' }\;(Q)\) is reflexive. Let the interpretation \(m\) interpret all existing symbols as \({ m' }\) does. Moreover, let \(({ x },{ y })\in {}m\;(R)\) precisely when \(\forall {}\;{ r }.\;{ m' }\;(Q)({ r },{ x })\Rightarrow { m' }\;(Q)({ r },{ y })\). \(m\;(R)\) is reflexive (by reflexivity of implication) and transitive (by transitivity of implication). We have to show that \(\lnot {}m\;(Q)({ x },{ y })\) implies \(\lnot {}m\;(R)({ x },{ y })\), which is the same as showing that \(\forall {}\;{ r }.\;m\;(Q)({ r },{ x })\Rightarrow m\;(Q)({ r },{ y })\) implies \(m\;(Q)({ x },{ y })\), which is true because \(m\;(Q)\) is reflexive. Thus we also have \(m\models { H }\). \(\square \)

7 Experimental Results

We evaluate the effects of the different axiomatizations using three different resolution based theorem provers, E 2.0 [10] (with the xAuto and tAuto options), Vampire 4.0 [7] (with the casc mode option), Spass 3.9 [13] (with the Auto option, which activates chaining in the presence of transitive predicates), and two SMT-solvers, Z3 4.5 [4] and CVC4 1.5 [2]. The experiments were performed on a PC with a 2xQuad Core Intel Xeon E5620 processor with 24 GB physical memory, running at 2.4 GHz, with Ubuntu 12.04. We use a time limit of 5 min on each problem.
We started from a set of 13410 test problems from the TPTP, listed as Unsatisfiable, Theorem or Unknown or Open (leaving out the very large theories)4. For each problem, a new theory was generated for each applicable transformation. For most problems, no relation matching any of the given criteria was detected, and thus no new theories were produced for these problems. In total, 2007 problems were found to include one or more transitive relations and could thus be used with at least one of the presented transformations. 130 of these problems are listed as Unknown, and an additional 172 problems have rating 1.0. No problem in the resulting set of problems is listed as Open.
The experimental results are summarized in Fig. 6.
Overall, the results vary between each transformation and reasoning tool. For many of the transformations, we do not gain any solved problems without also losing some. A time-slicing strategy can be advantageous, were the reasoning tool is run on both the original and the transformed problem, with a suitably chosen time-limit for each. Z3 turns out to work well on ordified problems, where it can make use of its built in strategies for arithmetic. E did not benefit from any of the transformations, and a large portion of the problems became unsolvable. One may have expected better results for equalification, since introducing equality in place of each occurrence of an equivalence relation seems suitable for an equational theorem prover. However, E performs well already on the untreated problems with equivalence relations, leaving little room for improvement. Vampire has the least difference in performance before and after the transformations.
In order to make a comparison between the transformations and evaluate what transformation works best for each kind of transitive relation, we partition the test problems into different subsets (Fig. 7). These subsets are defined by the discovered properties of the transitive relation. A problem can appear in several subsets if the problem includes several transitive relations having different properties. This is the case for 156 problems. Apart from such special cases, the subsets are disjoint. Firstly, we divide the problems into two sets, one where the transitive relation is found to be total (or strictly total, as in the case of a negated total order), and one where this was not the case. We use the notation PC to denote the subset of problems with transitive relations with no syntactic evidence of the property P.
The problems in TotalC are further divided into four groups, depending on if they contain a transitive relation that is found to be reflexive and/or symmetric. The problems containing a total relation are partitioned into two sets: problems with one or more total order (i.e. total, transitive and antisymmetric), and problems with relations that are total and transitive but lack the antisymmetry property (labelled as “other” in the diagram). Fig. 7 shows each subset with its number of problems and number of rating 1 problems, and the transformations that are applicable for that subset. For example, a problem with a transitive relation that is in TotalC, ReflexiveC and Symmetric has the applicable transformations Pequalification and Detransification, as shown in the bottom left corner of the diagram. The number of rating 1 problems in each subset can give an indication of the difficulty of dealing with different kinds of transitive relations. Problems with equivalence relations are typically less difficult than problems with partial equivalence relations, however it is hard to tell if the difficulty of a problem is related to the transitive relation or has other reasons.

7.1 Detransification

Detransification is the only transformation applicable on all 2007 test problems with transitive relations. As can be seen in Fig. 6, the benefits of detransification varies with the theorem prover and problem. The SMT-solvers profit the most from this transformation, however, big differences can be seen in the different subsets. Figure 18 presents an overview of the effects on solving times for each theorem prover in the evaluation. For all of the theorem provers, detransification lets us prove some problems that we could not previously, but some problems also become unsolvable within the time limit.
Figure 8 presents the results of detransification on each of the subsets defined in Fig. 7. Here we can get an indication of what problems detransification is useful for and what kind of problems tend to become harder after the transformation. For E, the results generally become worse after detransification, even though some new problems become solvable, including one with rating 1. For Vampire, detransification improves the results on problems with partial orders and partial equivalence relations. These subsets have a relatively low success rate before the transformations. On the other subsets, the results stay fairly stable. For Spass, partial equivalences and strict partial orders benefit the most from detransification, while the other subsets show mixed results. Both SMT-solvers, Z3 and CVC4, show improved results on the transformed equivalence relations and partial equivalence relation. The theorem provers performed well on these problems already before the transformation and thus have less room for improvement. For partial orders and strict partial orders, the results are mixed, however more is gained than what is lost. Total orders and other transitive relations do not benefit from detransification using any of the reasoning tools in our evaluation.

7.2 Detransification with Reflexivity

The use of detransification with reflexivity is limited to transitive relations that are reflexive. It shows worse results than detransification without reflexivity on all applicable subsets for all of the tested tools. This is especially true for the SMT-solvers, for which many problems become unsolvable. The results on each applicable subset is shown in Fig. 9

7.3 Pequalification

Pequalification is applicable on any relation that is transitive and symmetric, i.e. both equivalence relations and partial equivalence relations. The results on these subsets are presented in Fig. 10, which also shows the results of the variant of pequalification with the added idempotency axiom. SMT-solvers benefit the most from pequalification, especially Z3 on the set of problems with equivalence relations. All of the tested reasoning tools perform about the same or worse given this extra axiom.
Comparing pequalification with detransification, detransification is clearly much better for partial equivalence relations, while for equivalence relations it is not as clear which transformation one should pick. Pequalification without idempotency seems to be a good choice on equivalence relations for SMT-solvers, especially for Z3.

7.4 Equalification

Equalification is applicable only to problems that contain equivalence relations. It performs slightly worse or about the same compared to pequalification, which is more general. Like pequalification, it shows the best results combined with the SMT solvers. Adding an idempotency axiom typically makes the results slightly worse, with E showing the most significant change. The results of equalification and equalification with idempotency are presented in Fig. 11.

7.5 Ordification

Since ordification uses arithmetic, it is only applicable with Vampire (in TFF format) and Z3 and CVC4 (in SMT format). The original problems were transformed into TFF and SMT as well, in order to achieve a fair comparison, avoiding the effects that the change of input format may have on the results. Ordification is applicable only on the set of problems containing total orders. Ordification improved the results significantly for both Z3 and CVC4, while Vampire performs about the same as before the transformation.
We can compare ordification with detransification, which is the only other transformation that is applicable on total orders. Similarly to ordification, detransification does not have any significant impact on the results for either of CVC4 or Vampire on total orders. For Z3, ordification is clearly the best choice. Note however that Z3 shows worse results than CVC4 and Vampire prior to the transformation. After ordification, the three tools solve about the same number of problems. The results are presented in Fig. 12.

7.6 Problems with more than One Kind of Transitive Relation

156 of the problems in our evaluation contain more than one kind of transitive relation. 140 of them contain a partial equivalence relation and a strict partial order. 14 contain an equivalence relation and a partial order, and two problems contain a partial equivalence relation and a relation that is total and transitive. Almost half of these problems are hard, with rating 1 in the TPTP.
For the 140 problems with a partial equivalence and a strict partial order, we found that applying detransification to all of the transitive relations gave the best results. For the 14 problems with equivalence relation and a partial order, applying equalification on the equivalence relation and detransification on the partial order was the best, in particular for the SMT-solvers. The 2 remaining problems with multiple kinds of transitive relations are both labelled as Unknown, and were not solved before nor after any choice of transformation.

7.7 Time-Slicing

As can be seen in Figs. 18, 19, 20, 21 and 22, problems are typically solved within the first half of the 5 min time-limit or less. By splitting the time equally between the original version of the problem and the applicable transformations can thus in many cases improve the success rate. This was the case for Spass, CVC4 and Z3. For Vampire (which has its own built-in time-slicing strategies), many problems were solved towards the end of the 5 min, and time-slicing between transformations was thus less favourable. For E, whose advantages of the transformations were quite limited, the problems that did become solvable after a transformation were solved in a relatively short time. The best results were achieved by allowing 10 s on each applicable transformation, and the remaining time on the original problem.

7.8 Optimal Strategies

We present for each tool an optimal strategy, that is given by identifying for each subset the transformation or combination of transformations that maximises the total number of solved problems. Since the results are based on the limited set of problems in the current TPTP library, we do not provide a universal method, but rather an idea of how parameters can be tuned to improve the results.
In Sect. 7.5, we transformed the original problem into the same format as the ordified problem (SMT format for Z3 and CVC4, and TFF format for Vampire), to focus on the effects of ordification alone. In this section we are concerned with how the results of the problems in the TPTP library can be improved. We therefore compare all results of the transformations (including ordification) with the original TPTP problem given in CNF-format. This makes a difference for Z3, which performs better on the original problems in CNF format than the problems transformed into SMT. This is the reason why Z3 solves 31 new problems after ordification in Fig. 16 but 50 new problems in Fig. 12. We omit detransification with reflexivity and the idempotency version of equalification and pequalification in the diagrams below, as these transformations did not contribute to the overall results.

7.8.1 E

E did not have any major benefits from any of the transformations. However, with time-slicing we can avoid a lot of the bad effects of a transformation, while still keeping the results that were improved. For E, the best results were achieved when allowing 10 s on each transformed problem and the remaining time on the original problem. This is based on a time-limit of 5 min. Fig. 13 show the subsets on which there was a transformation that solved new problems. With this strategy, we gain a total of 10 solved problems, 7 with equivalence relations and 3 with partial orders. On the remaining subsets there is no transformation that increases the success rate compared to the original, but splitting does not decrease it.

7.8.2 Vampire

For Vampire, detransification is the best choice for both partial orders and partial equivalence relations. A majority of the problems solved after detransification but not before took a long time, making time-slicing less favorable. For the other subsets, Vampire is the most successful on the original problems. Using detransification on partial equivalences and partial orders, and no transformation otherwise, we gain 39 solved problems and lose 6.

7.8.3 Spass

For Spass, the best results for transitive and reflexive relations (i.e. equivalences and partial orders) were given by spending 10 s on each of the applicable transformations, and the remaining time on the original problem. For the remaining subsets, splitting evenly between the applicable transformations and untransformed problems solves the most problems. The 8 new solved problems with a partial equivalence also have a strict partial order, and thus are contained in the 43 new problems that were solved in the partial orders subset. In total, the optimal strategy solves 75 new problems, while it loses 15.

7.8.4 Z3

For Z3, the best strategy is to split the time evenly between the original problem and all of the applicable transformations. Spending 10 s on each applicable transformation and the remaining time on the original problem gives very similar results. In total, we solve 135 new problems compared to the original, and lose 6. 21 of the newly solved problems are in overlapping subsets (containing more than one kind of transitive relation).

7.8.5 CVC4

For CVC4, splitting evenly between the original problem and all of the applicable transformations gives the best results. 19 of the newly solved problems are overlapping; 16 problems have both a partial equivalence and a strict partial order. 3 of the problems have an equivalence relation and a partial order. The total gain of the optimal strategy is 83 problems, and the loss is 2 problems.

8 Discussion and Conclusions

We have presented 6 transformations that can be applied to theories with certain transitive relations: equalification, pequalification, ordification, maxification, detransification, and detransification with reflexivity. We have also created a method for syntactic discovery of binary relations where these transformations are applicable.
For users of reasoning tools that create their own theories, it is clear that they should consider using one or more of the proposed alternative treatments when writing theories. For all of our methods, there are existing theories for which some provers performed better on these theories than others. In particular, there exist 5 TPTP problems that are now solvable that weren’t previously. These are FLD012-2 (solved by E with detransification), SEU322+2 (Solved by Vampire and Z3 with detransification), SEU270+2 (solved by CVC4 and Z3 with detransification), SEU372+2 (solved by Vampire with detransification) and LDA005-1 (solved by Z3 with ordification).
For implementers of reasoning tools, our conclusions are less clear. For some combinations of treatments and provers (such as transification for Vampire, and equalification for Z3), overall results are clearly better, and we would thus recommend these treatments as preprocessors for these provers. Some more combinations of treatments and provers lend themselves to a time slicing strategy that can solve strictly more problems, and could be integrated in a natural way in provers that already have the time slicing machinery in place.

9 Future Work

There are many other relations that are more or less common that could benefit from an alternative treatment like the transformations described in this paper. In particular, maxification seems to be an idea that could be applied to binary relations that are weaker than total orders, which may make this treatment more effective. But there are also other, non-transitive relations that are of interest.
There are other kinds of relations than binary relations. For example, we can have an ternary relation that behaves as an equivalence relation in its 2nd and 3rd argument. An alternative treatment of this relation would be to introduce a binary function symbol \(rep\). We do not know whether or not this occurs often, and if it is a good idea to treat higher-arity relational symbols specially in this way.
Lastly, we would like to look at how these ideas could be used inside a theorem prover; as soon as the prover discovers that a relation is an equivalence relation or a total order, one of our transformations could be applied, on the fly. The details of how to do this remain to be investigated.

Acknowledgements

We thank Nicholas Smallbone and the anonyous referees for discussions and useful suggestions on earlier versions of this paper.

Open Access

This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (http://​creativecommons.​org/​licenses/​by/​4.​0/​), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons license, and indicate if changes were made.
Open AccessThis article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article’s Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article’s Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://​creativecommons.​org/​licenses/​by/​4.​0/​.

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Fußnoten
1
Throughout the paper, we use the word theory to simply mean “set of formulas”.
 
2
For the statistics in this paper, we decided to only look at unsorted TPTP problems with 10.000 clauses or less.
 
3
We write \(m\;(R)\) for the interpretation of symbol \(R\) in the model \(m\).
 
4
Theories with more than 10.000 clauses were considered "very large" and we chose to leave them out of these experiments, because they were impractical to deal with. We have also evaluated the transformations on Satisfiable/Countersatisfiable problems, but there were too few problems for the results to be significant, and the results were also mostly negative.
 
Literatur
1.
Zurück zum Zitat Leo Bachmair and Harald Ganzinger. Ordered chaining calculi for first-order theories of transitive relations. Journal of the ACM, 45(6), 1007–1049, 1998MathSciNetCrossRef Leo Bachmair and Harald Ganzinger. Ordered chaining calculi for first-order theories of transitive relations. Journal of the ACM, 45(6), 1007–1049, 1998MathSciNetCrossRef
2.
Zurück zum Zitat Barrett, C., Conway, C.L., Deters, M., Hadarean, L., Jovanović, D., King, T., Reynolds, A., Tinelli, C.: CVC4. In: Proceedings of the 23rd International Conference on Computer Aided Verification (CAV’11). Springer, Berlin (2011) Barrett, C., Conway, C.L., Deters, M., Hadarean, L., Jovanović, D., King, T., Reynolds, A., Tinelli, C.: CVC4. In: Proceedings of the 23rd International Conference on Computer Aided Verification (CAV’11). Springer, Berlin (2011)
3.
Zurück zum Zitat Cristiá, M., Rossi, G.: A decision procedure for sets, binary relations and partial functions. In: Proceedings of the 28th Conference on Computer Aided Verification (CAV’16). Springer, Berlin (2016) Cristiá, M., Rossi, G.: A decision procedure for sets, binary relations and partial functions. In: Proceedings of the 28th Conference on Computer Aided Verification (CAV’16). Springer, Berlin (2016)
4.
Zurück zum Zitat de Moura, L., Bjørner, N.: Z3: An efficient SMT solver. In: Proceedings of the 14th International Conference on Tools and Algorithms for the Construction and Analysis of Systems (TACAS’08). Springer (2008) de Moura, L., Bjørner, N.: Z3: An efficient SMT solver. In: Proceedings of the 14th International Conference on Tools and Algorithms for the Construction and Analysis of Systems (TACAS’08). Springer (2008)
5.
Zurück zum Zitat Hillenbrand, T., Piskac, R., Waldmann, U., Weidenbach, C.: From search to computation: Redundancy criteria and simplification at work. In: Programming Logics: Essays in Memory of Harald Ganzinger, pp. 169–193. Springer, Berlin (2013) Hillenbrand, T., Piskac, R., Waldmann, U., Weidenbach, C.: From search to computation: Redundancy criteria and simplification at work. In: Programming Logics: Essays in Memory of Harald Ganzinger, pp. 169–193. Springer, Berlin (2013)
6.
Zurück zum Zitat Horrocks, I., Gough, G.: Description logics with transitive roles. Descr. Logics 9(3), 385–410 (1997) Horrocks, I., Gough, G.: Description logics with transitive roles. Descr. Logics 9(3), 385–410 (1997)
7.
Zurück zum Zitat Kovács, L., Voronkov, A.: First-order theorem proving and vampire. In: Proceedings of the 25th Conference on Computer Aided Verification (CAV’13). Springer, Berlin (2013) Kovács, L., Voronkov, A.: First-order theorem proving and vampire. In: Proceedings of the 25th Conference on Computer Aided Verification (CAV’13). Springer, Berlin (2013)
8.
Zurück zum Zitat Meng, B., Reynolds, A., Tinelli, C., Barrett, C.: Relational constraint solving in SMT. In: de Moura, L. (ed.) Proceedings of the 26nd Conference on Automated Deduction (CADE-26). Springer, Berlin (2017) Meng, B., Reynolds, A., Tinelli, C., Barrett, C.: Relational constraint solving in SMT. In: de Moura, L. (ed.) Proceedings of the 26nd Conference on Automated Deduction (CADE-26). Springer, Berlin (2017)
9.
Zurück zum Zitat Schmidt, R.A., Hustadt, U.: The axiomatic translation principle for modal logic. ACM Trans. Comput. Logic 8(4), 19 (2007)MathSciNetCrossRef Schmidt, R.A., Hustadt, U.: The axiomatic translation principle for modal logic. ACM Trans. Comput. Logic 8(4), 19 (2007)MathSciNetCrossRef
12.
Zurück zum Zitat Torlak, E., Jackson, D.: Kodkod: a relational model finder. In: Proceedings of the 13th International Conference on Tools and Algorithms for the Construction and Analysis of Systems (TACAS’07). Springer, Berlin (2007) Torlak, E., Jackson, D.: Kodkod: a relational model finder. In: Proceedings of the 13th International Conference on Tools and Algorithms for the Construction and Analysis of Systems (TACAS’07). Springer, Berlin (2007)
13.
Zurück zum Zitat Weidenbach, C., Dimova, D., Fietzke, A., Kumar, R., Suda, M., Wischnewski, P.: Spass version 3.5. In: Proceedings of the 22nd Conference on Automated Deduction (CADE-22). Springer, Berlin (2009) Weidenbach, C., Dimova, D., Fietzke, A., Kumar, R., Suda, M., Wischnewski, P.: Spass version 3.5. In: Proceedings of the 22nd Conference on Automated Deduction (CADE-22). Springer, Berlin (2009)
Metadaten
Titel
Handling Transitive Relations in First-Order Automated Reasoning
verfasst von
Koen Claessen
Ann Lillieström
Publikationsdatum
09.09.2021
Verlag
Springer Netherlands
Erschienen in
Journal of Automated Reasoning / Ausgabe 8/2021
Print ISSN: 0168-7433
Elektronische ISSN: 1573-0670
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10817-021-09605-z

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 8/2021

Journal of Automated Reasoning 8/2021 Zur Ausgabe