Skip to main content
Erschienen in: Social Choice and Welfare 4/2014

01.12.2014

On the optimal composition of committees

verfasst von: Ruth Ben-Yashar, Leif Danziger

Erschienen in: Social Choice and Welfare | Ausgabe 4/2014

Einloggen

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

This paper derives a simple characterization of how to optimally divide an organization’s experts into different decision-making committees. The focus is on many three-member committees that make decisions by a simple majority rule. We find that the allocation of experts to committees is optimal if and only if it minimizes the sum of the products of the experts’ skills in each committee. As a result, given the experts of any two committees, the product of the experts’ skills should be as similar as possible in the two committees, and it is never optimal to have the three worst experts in one committee and the three best experts in another.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Fußnoten
1
See Grofman and Feld (1988), Young (1995), Ben-Yashar and Nitzan (1997), Berend and Sapir (2007), Dietrich and List (2008, 2013a), and Peleg and Zamir (2012). Further, Ahn and Oliveros (2010), Bozbay et al. (2011), and De Clippel and Eliaz (2012) study how to efficiently aggregate judgments when several issues are involved, as a link may then exist between the optimal decision for each issue. Their concern is whether the aggregation should be based on premise or outcome, and about the associated doctrinal paradox.
 
2
As, for example, in a legal system where decisions are made by courts having three judges and where judges can be either more experienced or less experienced.
 
3
Thus, there are at most
$$\begin{aligned} \frac{(3Z)!}{Z!(3!)^{Z}} \end{aligned}$$
possible compositions of committees in terms of the experts’ abilities.
 
4
This is equivalent to maximizing the expected number of correct decisions. Given our framework, it is a Nash equilibrium and therefore reasonable to assume that the experts vote according to their true assessment, i.e., informatively (Austen-Smith and Banks 1996; Ben-Yashar and Milchtaich 2007). Under other circumstances, strategic considerations may influence the experts’ voting behavior (Feddersen and Pesendorfer 1998; Dekel and Piccione 2000; Austen-Smith and Feddersen 2006; Gerardi and Yariv 2007). With the experts voting informatively and deciding by a simple majority rule, our results hold whether the proposals are independent or dependent. Thus, there is no need to assume even logical independence of the proposals (Dietrich and List 2013b).
 
5
That is,
$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial ^{2}\left[ (1/Z)\sum \limits _{c_{z}\in c}G(c_{z})\right] }{\partial q_{i}\partial q_{i^{\prime }}}<0 \end{aligned}$$
if expert \(i\) and expert \(i^{\prime }\) are members of the same committee.
 
6
To see this, suppose that \(Z=2\) and that the six experts have different skills. Furthermore, assume that \(q_{1}q_{2}=q_{3}q_{4}\), \(q_{5}=(q_{1}q_{2})^{1/2}\), and \(q_{6}=(q_{1}q_{2})^{1/2+\epsilon }\), where \(\epsilon >0\). Then,
$$\begin{aligned} q_{1}q_{2}(q_{1}q_{2})^{1/2}+q_{3}q_{4}(q_{1}q_{2})^{1/2+\epsilon }&= q_{1}q_{2}(q_{1}q_{2})^{1/2+\epsilon }+q_{3}q_{4}(q_{1}q_{2})^{1/2}\\ \Leftrightarrow q_{1}q_{2}q_{5}+q_{3}q_{4}q_{6}&= q_{1}q_{2}q_{6}+q_{3}q_{4}q_{5}. \end{aligned}$$
Hence, the partition \(\{1,2,5\}\) and \(\{3,4,6\}\) of experts and the partition \(\{1,2,6\}\) and \(\{3,4,5\}\) of experts have the same sum of the products of the experts’ skills in each committee. Furthermore, if \(\epsilon \) is sufficiently small, the sum is smaller than for any other partition. Accordingly, there are two optimal compositions of the committees.
 
7
Preferably, such “experts” should be prevented from being committee members or should be made to abstain in the voting. In a model with costly voting, Börgers (2004) shows that abstentions should be allowed.
 
8
The second-order conditions for a minimum are satisfied.
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Ahn DS, Oliveros S (2010) The Condorcet jur(ies) theorem. Working paper Ahn DS, Oliveros S (2010) The Condorcet jur(ies) theorem. Working paper
Zurück zum Zitat Austen-Smith D, Banks JS (1996) Information aggregation, rationality, and the Condorcet jury theorem. Am Polit Sci Rev 90:34–45CrossRef Austen-Smith D, Banks JS (1996) Information aggregation, rationality, and the Condorcet jury theorem. Am Polit Sci Rev 90:34–45CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Austen-Smith D, Feddersen T (2006) Deliberation, preference uncertainty, and voting rules. Am Polit Sci Rev 100:209–218CrossRef Austen-Smith D, Feddersen T (2006) Deliberation, preference uncertainty, and voting rules. Am Polit Sci Rev 100:209–218CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Ben-Yashar R, Danziger L (2011) Symmetric and asymmetric committees. J Math Econ 47:440–447CrossRef Ben-Yashar R, Danziger L (2011) Symmetric and asymmetric committees. J Math Econ 47:440–447CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Ben-Yashar R, Milchtaich I (2007) First and second best voting rules in committees. Social Choice Welf 29:453–486CrossRef Ben-Yashar R, Milchtaich I (2007) First and second best voting rules in committees. Social Choice Welf 29:453–486CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Ben-Yashar R, Nitzan S (1997) The optimal decision rule for fixed-size committees in dichotomous choice situations: the general result. Int Econ Rev 38:175–186CrossRef Ben-Yashar R, Nitzan S (1997) The optimal decision rule for fixed-size committees in dichotomous choice situations: the general result. Int Econ Rev 38:175–186CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Berend D, Sapir L (2007) Monotonicity in Condorcet’s jury theorem with dependent voters. Social Choice Welf 28:507–528CrossRef Berend D, Sapir L (2007) Monotonicity in Condorcet’s jury theorem with dependent voters. Social Choice Welf 28:507–528CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bozbay I, Dietrich F, Peters H (2011) Judgment aggregation in search for the truth. Working paper Bozbay I, Dietrich F, Peters H (2011) Judgment aggregation in search for the truth. Working paper
Zurück zum Zitat Condorcet NC (1785) Essai sur l’application de l’analyse à la probabilitè des dècisions rendues à la pluralitè des voix, Paris. In: McLean I, Hewitt F (1994) translators. L’Impremerie Royale, Paris Condorcet NC (1785) Essai sur l’application de l’analyse à la probabilitè des dècisions rendues à la pluralitè des voix, Paris. In: McLean I, Hewitt F (1994) translators. L’Impremerie Royale, Paris
Zurück zum Zitat De Clippel G, Eliaz K (2012) Premise-based versus outcome-based information aggregation. Working paper De Clippel G, Eliaz K (2012) Premise-based versus outcome-based information aggregation. Working paper
Zurück zum Zitat Dekel E, Piccione M (2000) Sequential voting procedures in symmetric binary elections. J Polit Econ 108:34–55CrossRef Dekel E, Piccione M (2000) Sequential voting procedures in symmetric binary elections. J Polit Econ 108:34–55CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Dietrich F, List C (2008) Judgment aggregation without full rationality. Social Choice Welf 31:15–39CrossRef Dietrich F, List C (2008) Judgment aggregation without full rationality. Social Choice Welf 31:15–39CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Dietrich F, List C (2013a) Propositionwise judgment aggregation: the general case. Social Choice Welf 40:1067–1095CrossRef Dietrich F, List C (2013a) Propositionwise judgment aggregation: the general case. Social Choice Welf 40:1067–1095CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Dietrich F, List C (2013b) Probabilistic opinion pooling generalized-part one: general agendas. Working paper Dietrich F, List C (2013b) Probabilistic opinion pooling generalized-part one: general agendas. Working paper
Zurück zum Zitat Feddersen T, Pesendorfer W (1998) Convicting the innocent: the inferiority of unanimous jury verdicts. Am Polit Sci Rev 92:23–35CrossRef Feddersen T, Pesendorfer W (1998) Convicting the innocent: the inferiority of unanimous jury verdicts. Am Polit Sci Rev 92:23–35CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Gerardi D, Yariv L (2007) Deliberative voting. J Econ Theory 134:317–338CrossRef Gerardi D, Yariv L (2007) Deliberative voting. J Econ Theory 134:317–338CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Grofman B, Feld SL (1988) Rousseau’s general will: a Condorcet perspective. Am Polit Sci Rev 82:567–576CrossRef Grofman B, Feld SL (1988) Rousseau’s general will: a Condorcet perspective. Am Polit Sci Rev 82:567–576CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Peleg B, Zamir S (2012) Extending the Condorcet jury theorem to a general dependent jury. Social Choice Welf 39:91–125CrossRef Peleg B, Zamir S (2012) Extending the Condorcet jury theorem to a general dependent jury. Social Choice Welf 39:91–125CrossRef
Metadaten
Titel
On the optimal composition of committees
verfasst von
Ruth Ben-Yashar
Leif Danziger
Publikationsdatum
01.12.2014
Verlag
Springer Berlin Heidelberg
Erschienen in
Social Choice and Welfare / Ausgabe 4/2014
Print ISSN: 0176-1714
Elektronische ISSN: 1432-217X
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-014-0805-z

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 4/2014

Social Choice and Welfare 4/2014 Zur Ausgabe

Premium Partner