Skip to main content
Erschienen in: Quality & Quantity 2/2015

01.03.2015

Parsimony and Causality

verfasst von: Michael Baumgartner

Erschienen in: Quality & Quantity | Ausgabe 2/2015

Einloggen

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

This paper takes issue with the current tendency in the literature on Qualitative Comparative Analysis (QCA) to settle for so-called intermediate solution formulas, in which parsimony is not maximized. I show that there is a tight conceptual connection between parsimony and causality: only maximally parsimonious solution formulas reflect causal structures. However, in order to maximize parsimony, QCA—due to its reliance on Quine-McCluskey optimization (Q-M)—is often forced to introduce untenable simplifying assumptions. The paper ends by demonstrating that there is an alternative Boolean method for causal data analysis, viz. Coincidence Analysis (CNA), that replaces Q-M by a different optimization algorithm and, thereby, succeeds in consistently maximizing parsimony without reliance on untenable assumptions.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Fußnoten
1
In this paper, the notion of a model is used in terms of a full specification of the functional dependencies among endogenous and exogenous factors. In the QCA literature, a model is sometimes (e.g. Wright and Boudet 2012) simply taken to be a selection of endogenous and exogenous factors (without a specification of functional dependencies).
 
2
Some studies even settle for so-called conservative solution formulas with all redundancies remaining (cf. Grofman and Schneider 2009).
 
3
There also exist non-causal applications of QCA. For instance, Mendel and Korjani (2012) use QCA as a method for linguistic summarization, which is a data mining approach to extract patterns from databases. The goal of this approach is not to generate causal knowledge, causal explanations, or to test causal hypotheses; rather, it seeks to better understand and communicate about data. For such a purpose, solution formulas that are not maximally parsimonious may be very useful. Moreover, intermediate solutions may be informative with respect to correlations and associations among investigated factors; cf. e.g. (Grant, Morales, and Sallaz (2009), 344–345) who very explicitly abstain from causally interpreting intermediate solutions (though for different reasons than the ones advanced in this paper).
 
4
For a recent illustration of the debates between these two theoretical camps see Glynn (2013) and Ney (2009).
 
5
Usually, in the prose around solution formulas in QCA studies only necessary conditions that consist of single factors are explicitly labeled “necessary conditions”. (A commendable exception is Bol and Luppi (2013), who systematize the search for complex necessary conditions within the QCA framework.) In fact, however, every QCA solution formula that identifies complex sufficient conditions for the absence of an effect is tantamount to a solution formula that identifies a complex necessary condition for the presence of the effect (by contraposition), and vice versa. For instance, a formula that identifies \(AC\) and \(\overline{D}\) as two alternative sufficient conditions for \(\overline{E}\) is logically equivalent to a formula that identifies \(\overline{A}D \vee \overline{C}D\) as necessary condition for \(E\). Disjunctive necessary conditions can be interpreted as imposing restrictions on the space of alternative causes of an effect: in the structure represented by (1), \(E\) has exactly three alternative causes.
 
6
In the QCA literature, two rows \(c_i\) and \(c_h\) in a truth-table such that one and the same configuration of conditions is combined with the presence of the outcome in \(c_i\) and with its absence in \(c_h\) are often very misleadingly called “contradictory” (cf. e.g. Rihoux and De Meur 2009; Schneider and Wagemann 2012 §5.1; Rubinson 2013). In fact, however, such a pair of rows is far from being contradictory, rather, it merely entails that the relevant configuration of conditions is neither sufficient for the presence nor for the absence of the outcome.
 
7
The QCA solution formulas in this article were built using the \(R\)-implementation of QCA by Alrik Thiem and Adrian Duşa, version 1.0-5 (2013a, b).
 
8
Without providing any reasons, (Rubinson (2013), 2866) rightly deplores the fact that “far too many researchers automatically pick the intermediate solution, assuming that it must be best”. The most straightforward reason why a general preference of intermediate solutions is deplorable is simply that these solutions are not (causally) explanatory.
 
9
A causal dependence among investigated conditions is but one reason why certain remainders turn out to be impossible—logical, conceptual, or mereological dependencies being further reasons. Thus, the arrow from \(A\) to \(C\) in Fig. 1 could also be interpreted in terms of such a non-causal form of dependence.
 
10
In fact, the disjunction of solution terms of the conservative formula (4) is logically equivalent to the disjunction of configurations in rows \(c_1\) to \(c_5\) and \(c_7\) in Table 1, which are the configurations that are sufficient for \(E\) in that table. Neither the intermediate nor the parsimonious solution—(6) and (5)—preserve this logical equivalence.
 
11
(Eliason and Stryker (2009), 26) implement a very analogous minimization idea in the context of a goodness-of-fit test for fuzzy-set solutions.
 
12
Note that CNA does not preclude the addition of counterfactual configurations; it just does not require it. If there are good theoretical grounds for counterfactually supplementing the data, CNA does not prevent the researcher from doing so. Whereas in the case of QCA it is the algorithmic machinery of the method that calls for the introduction of counterfactual configurations in order to eliminate all redundancies from solution formulas, CNA leaves counterfactual considerations entirely up to the researcher’s background theory.
 
13
The fact that QCA’s \(\mathcal {S}_3\) and CNA infer the same causal model for outcome \(E\) from Table 1 does not indicate that corresponding inferences are based on the same or even related assumptions. One and the same conclusion can be inferred from very different assumptions. For instance, “Socrates is mortal” can be inferred from the assumptions “Socrates is a man” and “All men are mortal”, or from “All immortal things are angels” and “Socrates is not an angel”, or from any contradiction, e.g. from “It rains and it does not rain”. A conclusion is established if it is not only validly inferred from a set of assumptions, but if the latter are moreover cogently justifiable.
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Baumgartner, M.: Regularity theories reassessed. Philosophia 36, 327–354 (2008) Baumgartner, M.: Regularity theories reassessed. Philosophia 36, 327–354 (2008)
Zurück zum Zitat Baumgartner, M.: Inferring causal complexity. Sociol. Methods Res. 38, 71–101 (2009a) Baumgartner, M.: Inferring causal complexity. Sociol. Methods Res. 38, 71–101 (2009a)
Zurück zum Zitat Baumgartner, M.: Uncovering deterministic causal structures: a Boolean approach. Synthese 170, 71–96 (2009b) Baumgartner, M.: Uncovering deterministic causal structures: a Boolean approach. Synthese 170, 71–96 (2009b)
Zurück zum Zitat Baumgartner, M.: A regularity theoretic approach to actual causation. Erkenntnis 78, 85–109 (2013)CrossRef Baumgartner, M.: A regularity theoretic approach to actual causation. Erkenntnis 78, 85–109 (2013)CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Baumgartner, M. and R. Epple.: A Coincidence Analysis of a causal chain: the Swiss minaret vote. Sociol. Methods Res. (forthcoming) Baumgartner, M. and R. Epple.: A Coincidence Analysis of a causal chain: the Swiss minaret vote. Sociol. Methods Res. (forthcoming)
Zurück zum Zitat Bol, D., Luppi, F.: Confronting theories based on necessary relations: making the best of QCA possibilities. Polit. Res. Q. 66(1), 205–210 (2013) Bol, D., Luppi, F.: Confronting theories based on necessary relations: making the best of QCA possibilities. Polit. Res. Q. 66(1), 205–210 (2013)
Zurück zum Zitat Dowe, P.: Physical causation. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2000)CrossRef Dowe, P.: Physical causation. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2000)CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Eliason, S.R., Stryker, R.: Goodness-of-fit tests and descriptive measures in fuzzy-set analysis. Sociol. Methods Res. 38(1), 102–146 (2009)CrossRef Eliason, S.R., Stryker, R.: Goodness-of-fit tests and descriptive measures in fuzzy-set analysis. Sociol. Methods Res. 38(1), 102–146 (2009)CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Glynn, L.: Causal foundationalism, physical causation, and difference-making. Synthese 190(6), 1017–1037 (2013)CrossRef Glynn, L.: Causal foundationalism, physical causation, and difference-making. Synthese 190(6), 1017–1037 (2013)CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Grant, D., Morales, A., Sallaz, J.J.: Pathways to meaning: a new approach to studying emotions at work. Am. J. Sociol. 115, 327–364 (2009) Grant, D., Morales, A., Sallaz, J.J.: Pathways to meaning: a new approach to studying emotions at work. Am. J. Sociol. 115, 327–364 (2009)
Zurück zum Zitat Grofman, B., Schneider, C.Q.: An introduction to crisp set QCA, with a comparison to binary logistic regression. Polit. Res. Q. 62(4), 662–672 (2009)CrossRef Grofman, B., Schneider, C.Q.: An introduction to crisp set QCA, with a comparison to binary logistic regression. Polit. Res. Q. 62(4), 662–672 (2009)CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Mackie, J.L.: The cement of the universe. A study of causation. Clarendon Press, Oxford (1974) Mackie, J.L.: The cement of the universe. A study of causation. Clarendon Press, Oxford (1974)
Zurück zum Zitat Mahoney, J., Goertz, G.: A tale of two cultures: contrasting quantitative and qualitative research. Polit. Anal. 14, 227–249 (2006)CrossRef Mahoney, J., Goertz, G.: A tale of two cultures: contrasting quantitative and qualitative research. Polit. Anal. 14, 227–249 (2006)CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Mendel, J.M., Korjani, M.M.: Charles Ragin’s fuzzy set Qualitative Comparative Analysis (fsQCA) used for linguistic summarizations. Inf. Sci. 202, 1–23 (2012) Mendel, J.M., Korjani, M.M.: Charles Ragin’s fuzzy set Qualitative Comparative Analysis (fsQCA) used for linguistic summarizations. Inf. Sci. 202, 1–23 (2012)
Zurück zum Zitat Mumford, S., Anjum, R.L.: Getting causes from powers. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2011)CrossRef Mumford, S., Anjum, R.L.: Getting causes from powers. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2011)CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Ney, A.: Physical causation and difference-making. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 60(4), 737–764 (2009)CrossRef Ney, A.: Physical causation and difference-making. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 60(4), 737–764 (2009)CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Pearl, J.: Causality: models, reasoning, and inference. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2000) Pearl, J.: Causality: models, reasoning, and inference. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2000)
Zurück zum Zitat Psillos, S.: Causal pluralism. In: Vanderbeeken, R., D’Hooghe, B. (eds.) Worldviews, science and us: studies of analytical metaphysics, pp. 131–151. World Scientific Publishers, Singapore (2009) Psillos, S.: Causal pluralism. In: Vanderbeeken, R., D’Hooghe, B. (eds.) Worldviews, science and us: studies of analytical metaphysics, pp. 131–151. World Scientific Publishers, Singapore (2009)
Zurück zum Zitat Quine, W.v.O.: On cores and prime implicants of truth functions. Am. Math. Mon. 66, 755–760 (1959) Quine, W.v.O.: On cores and prime implicants of truth functions. Am. Math. Mon. 66, 755–760 (1959)
Zurück zum Zitat Ragin, C., Rihoux, B.: Qualitative Comparative Analysis (QCA): state of the art and prospects. Qual. Methods 2, 3–13 (2004) Ragin, C., Rihoux, B.: Qualitative Comparative Analysis (QCA): state of the art and prospects. Qual. Methods 2, 3–13 (2004)
Zurück zum Zitat Ragin, C.C.: The comparative method. University of California Press, Berkeley (1987) Ragin, C.C.: The comparative method. University of California Press, Berkeley (1987)
Zurück zum Zitat Ragin, C.C.: Fuzzy-set social science. University of Chicago Press, Chicago (2000) Ragin, C.C.: Fuzzy-set social science. University of Chicago Press, Chicago (2000)
Zurück zum Zitat Ragin, C.C.: Set relations in social research: evaluating their consistency and coverage. Polit. Anal 14, 291–310 (2006) Ragin, C.C.: Set relations in social research: evaluating their consistency and coverage. Polit. Anal 14, 291–310 (2006)
Zurück zum Zitat Ragin, C.C.: Fuzzy sets: calibration vs. measurement. In: Box-Steffensmeier, J., Brady, H.E., Collier, D. (eds.) The Oxford handbook of political methodology, pp. 174–198. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2008a) Ragin, C.C.: Fuzzy sets: calibration vs. measurement. In: Box-Steffensmeier, J., Brady, H.E., Collier, D. (eds.) The Oxford handbook of political methodology, pp. 174–198. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2008a)
Zurück zum Zitat Ragin, C.C.: Redesigning social inquiry: fuzzy sets and beyond. University of Chicago Press, Chicago (2008b)CrossRef Ragin, C.C.: Redesigning social inquiry: fuzzy sets and beyond. University of Chicago Press, Chicago (2008b)CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Ragin, C.C., Sonnett, J,: Between complexity and parsimony: limited diversity, counterfactual cases, and comparative analysis. In Vergleichen in der Politikwissenschaft, pp. 180–197. Wiesbaden: VS Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften (2005) Ragin, C.C., Sonnett, J,: Between complexity and parsimony: limited diversity, counterfactual cases, and comparative analysis. In Vergleichen in der Politikwissenschaft, pp. 180–197. Wiesbaden: VS Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften (2005)
Zurück zum Zitat Rihoux, B., De Meur, G.: Crisp-set Qualitative Comparative Analysis (csQCA). In: Rihoux, B., Ragin, C.C. (eds.) Configurational comparative methods: Qualitative Comparative Analysis (QCA) and related techniques, pp. 33–68. Sage, Thousand Oaks (2009) Rihoux, B., De Meur, G.: Crisp-set Qualitative Comparative Analysis (csQCA). In: Rihoux, B., Ragin, C.C. (eds.) Configurational comparative methods: Qualitative Comparative Analysis (QCA) and related techniques, pp. 33–68. Sage, Thousand Oaks (2009)
Zurück zum Zitat Rubinson, C.: Contradictions in fsQCA. Qual. Quant. 47(5), 2847–2867 (2013)CrossRef Rubinson, C.: Contradictions in fsQCA. Qual. Quant. 47(5), 2847–2867 (2013)CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Schneider, C.Q., Wagemann, C.: Set-theoretic methods: a user’s guide for Qualitative Comparative Analysis (QCA) and fuzzy-sets in the social sciences. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2012) Schneider, C.Q., Wagemann, C.: Set-theoretic methods: a user’s guide for Qualitative Comparative Analysis (QCA) and fuzzy-sets in the social sciences. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2012)
Zurück zum Zitat Skaaning, S.-E.: Assessing the robustness of crisp-set and fuzzy-set QCA results. Sociol. Methods Res. 40(2), 391–408 (2011)CrossRef Skaaning, S.-E.: Assessing the robustness of crisp-set and fuzzy-set QCA results. Sociol. Methods Res. 40(2), 391–408 (2011)CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Spirtes, P., Glymour, C., Scheines, R.: Causation, prediction, and search, 2nd edn. MIT Press, Cambridge (2000) Spirtes, P., Glymour, C., Scheines, R.: Causation, prediction, and search, 2nd edn. MIT Press, Cambridge (2000)
Zurück zum Zitat Suppes, P.: A probabilistic theory of causality. North Holland, Amsterdam (1970) Suppes, P.: A probabilistic theory of causality. North Holland, Amsterdam (1970)
Zurück zum Zitat Thiem, A., Baumgartner, M., Bol, D. (ms): Still lost in translation–a correction of three misunderstandings between configurational comparativists and regressional analysts Thiem, A., Baumgartner, M., Bol, D. (ms): Still lost in translation–a correction of three misunderstandings between configurational comparativists and regressional analysts
Zurück zum Zitat Thiem, A., Duşa, A.: QCA: a package for Qualitative Comparative Analysis. R. J. 5(1), 87–97 (2013a) Thiem, A., Duşa, A.: QCA: a package for Qualitative Comparative Analysis. R. J. 5(1), 87–97 (2013a)
Zurück zum Zitat Thiem, A., Duşa, A.: Qualitative Comparative Analysis with R: a user’s guide. Springer, New York (2013b) Thiem, A., Duşa, A.: Qualitative Comparative Analysis with R: a user’s guide. Springer, New York (2013b)
Zurück zum Zitat Woodward, J.: Making things happen. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2003) Woodward, J.: Making things happen. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2003)
Zurück zum Zitat Wright, R.A., Boudet, H.S.: To act or not to act: context, capability, and community response to environmental risk. Am. J. Sociol. 118(3), 728–777 (2012) Wright, R.A., Boudet, H.S.: To act or not to act: context, capability, and community response to environmental risk. Am. J. Sociol. 118(3), 728–777 (2012)
Metadaten
Titel
Parsimony and Causality
verfasst von
Michael Baumgartner
Publikationsdatum
01.03.2015
Verlag
Springer Netherlands
Erschienen in
Quality & Quantity / Ausgabe 2/2015
Print ISSN: 0033-5177
Elektronische ISSN: 1573-7845
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11135-014-0026-7

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 2/2015

Quality & Quantity 2/2015 Zur Ausgabe

Premium Partner