Skip to main content
Erschienen in: Public Organization Review 1/2023

Open Access 27.09.2022

Logics and Agency in Public Management Research

verfasst von: Tony Kinder, Jari Stenvall, Antti Talonen

Erschienen in: Public Organization Review | Ausgabe 1/2023

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

The article analyses the negative effects of the use of logics in public organisation research on active human agency. We build up a new conceptual model with which to approach logics in current research on organising public services; suggesting ways in which current models using logics in public organisation research can be strengthened. Our contribution is two-fold: we argue that Elder-Vass’ approach benefits from close synthesis with social learning theory (including recent thinking on trust, emotions, and distributed learning) and secondly, that grounding all usage of logics in logic-of-practice helps avoid a reification of logics and thirdly that situated learning better suits public organisation problem solving that the application of ‘new’ universal solutions.
Hinweise

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Introduction

A set of POR papers analysing COVID-19 responses, take as part of their explanatory tool kit how logics influences people and events. Christensen (2021) contrasts the logics flowing from March and Olsen’s (1983) homogeneous leadership, with those based on Selznick’s (1957) notion of homogeneous groups resulting in a situated logic of negotiation and compromise. Mattei and Vigevano’s (2021) analysis of the Italian COVID response interrelating national and local bodies, identifies a logic of underlaying policy integration cooperation that enhanced effectiveness. Mozumder (2021) suggests that the logic of learning from practice was made difficult in the UK because of diminished trust in agents and institutions.
Our paper picks up this issue of logics in how public organisations react to events. This is important as public managers increasingly focus on organising processes rather than organisational imperative: an essential change when most major policy responses now call for partnership, networks and/or ecosystem cooperation and integration. Situated and customised responses to events, taking advantage of available strengths and opportunities are perhaps particularly important, where user/client/customer feedback points to ways, as Normann (2002) notes, in which services can be improved. Our focus is on the potential conflict between the logics inherent in organisational form or organising in relation to the preferences of users and managers based on situated and social learning. Bourdieu (1984) and Bernstein (2000) emphasised how conduct of conduct rules (governance) are influenced by ‘soft’ socio-cultural practice, which they in turn reproduce and reshape. Faced with volatile and rapidly altering service environments, street-level decisions (Lipsky, 1980) can become patterned into ‘pop-up” governance-as-legitimacy (Laclau 1990).
Research about public organisations increasingly references logics: isomorphic logic (DiMaggio & Powell, 1983); public service logic (Ngoye et al., 2019; Osborne, 2017); management decision logics (Thornton et al., 2015) [ framing of public institutions and rules of the game logics (Scott, 2008); network management logics (Kooiman, 2003); and service-dominant logic (Lusch & Vargo, 2014, cf. Lopes & Alves, 2020). Bourdieu’s (1984) logic-of-practice is intended to ground logics in practice.
Logics is now a prominent idea in research on organisation from post-structural and socio-cultural process perspectives. March and Olsen (1989) for example, argued that logic of appropriateness has limited scope giving way to logic of consequences, apportioned by a hierarchy of logics. For social scientists seeking to generalise research results positing logics is an opportunity, provided as Kinder (2000) argues, they are recontextualised. Where logics are not re-grounded there is danger of assuming the future is dictated by yesterday, discounting human intervention. Determinism of this sort is a major issue in social research. Few social theorists now aim to ‘discover’ the ‘iron’ laws of society beloved by nineteenth century theorists. Logics properly applied are mediated by cognitive, emotional, (possibly) trusting people and especially so in services for people. As Jacobsen (2021) shows, in partnerships between the public and private sectors admixtures of potentially competing logics can be hybridised or combined to achieve public value.
Important thinkers criticise using logics from the perspective of diminishing agency include Wittgenstein (2001), Arendt (1951) and Chomsky (1969). Others highlight problems in agents choosing between multiple logics (Berman, 2012), or conflicting logics (Lounsbury, 2007), or over-reliance on logics to predict solutions (Dewey (1938), leading Archer (2000) and Toulmin (2003a, 2003b) for example to call for more research on the use of logics and contingency in social research.
Elder-Vass (2010) suggests a synthesis between Bourdieu’s (1990) idea of habitus as structuring thinking with Archer’s (2000) idea of inner conversations reflecting on choices in context. We find this synthesis inadequate for PM research since it unsatisfactorily addresses the complexity people face in public services and the nature of the learning processes they undertake, implying a clear view of how situated learning occurs and is used. Our research question is: are there negative effects of the use of logics in public organisation research on active human agency?
Our contribution is two-fold: we argue that Elder-Vass’ approach benefits from close synthesis with social learning theory (including recent thinking on trust, emotions, and distributed learning) and secondly, that grounding all usage of logics in logic-of-practice helps avoid a reification of logics. In pursuing these arguments, we build up a new conceptual model with which to approach logics in current research on organising in the public sector; suggesting ways in which frameworks using logics in can be strengthened.
The paper proceeds by exploring and defining the meaning of logics. Illustrating how the use of logics has become important in public organisation theory, one example being Bright’s (2021) recent use of Klijn et al., (2016) bureaucratic logic to analyse how organisational identity interrelates with motivation. We argue that logics are only valid when grounded in situated experience from logic-of-practice in a particular service setting. Since contexts and cultures differ, it cannot be assumed that logics applicable in one setting are appropriate to another. We give a short exposition of how active agents in a particular setting learn logics and apply them using Vygotsky’s social learning theory. We then consider how logics are currently deployed in public organisation research taking the example of Vargo and Lusch’s (2008) service-dominant logic and Klijn et al., (2016) and Kooiman’s (2003) network management. We show that in both cases logics are regarded as universals; there is an absence of active human agency in both cases. From this we argue for a review of how logics and active agency and currently used in public organisation research citing logics.

Logics: Genealogy and Use

Thornton and Ocasio (1999:804) define institutional logics as the socially constructed, historical patterns of material practices, assumptions, values, beliefs, and rules by which individuals produce and reproduce their material subsistence, organize time and space, and provide meaning to their social reality. Linking individual cognition to social structures they Thornton and Ocasio (2017) trace the idea to Selznick (1948) and later Zucker (1983), noting that Olson’s (1970) collective action emphasised individual consciousness and Fleck (1979) the notion of thought style as micro-social conditioning.
Douglas (1987:63) argued that organisations produce and reproduce sameness by embedding knowledge and when organisations interact, (DiMaggio & Powell, 1983) isomorphic logic diffused sameness, even according to Friedland and Alford (1991) across governances and between Governments. Wary of imitating symbolisms, Jackall (1988) argues imitating practice is more important; importantly suggesting the embedded agency is more important than imitative structures. Jackall’s framing of enablers and constraints continues to be cited though less is paid to the idea that only logics based on practice evidence have value.
Evidencing logics remains contentious for Toulmin (2003a:213) who says, Warm hearts allied with cool heads seek a middle way between the extremes of abstract theory and personal impulse, a wariness of deduced logics shared by Arendt (1958) who worries about thoughtlessness (1958:62) displacing empirical inquiry. Her emphasis on active agency (discussed below), including socially generated trust, is echoed by Popper (2007) who distrusts any logic not empirically founded.
Processes creating logics are subject to close scrutiny. For example, Van Benthem and Pacuit’s (2010) idea of temporal logics captures the point that logic in one time-frame may be non-logical in another. Epstein (1995) points to people internalising multiple logics and researchers need to justify their choices arguing that splitting and splicing of logics by agents are often unconscious. Kahneman and Tversky (1982) would agree, noting that slower (rational) selection of logics is post-facto justification of emotional preferences. Janik and Toulmin (1996) fear that transferring logics between locations is problematic.

Learning and Logics

The idea of logics is widespread in public organisation research in justifying interpretations and actions as the recent POR articiles demonstrate. Dunn and Jones (2010) argue that following the introduction of new public management (NPM), Doctors adopt a new array of logics, including management heuristics and processes. Suggesting Finnish Doctors are more accepting than their Norwegian colleagues of NPM, Berg et al. (2017) suggest this due to identity change. Also investigating Doctors and NPM, Berg et al. (2017) argue that identity change is more profound amongst Norwegian than Finnish Doctors, since the former have less acceptance of NPM logics. It is now common-place for researchers to follow Scott (2008) and speak of logics in and between organisations or follow Freidson (2001) and comment on changing logics within professions without citing grounded empirical evidence. Bjerregaard (2011:195) argues that organisational logics are derived from institutional logics, giving a hierarchical authority of logics: these hierarchies of logics he says are somehow learned and accepted as justifying actions.
This short review supports our argument that new research into the use of logics in public organisation research is needed. Bourdieu (1990) and Zacka (2017) would support this conclusion; they draw attention to logic-of-practice – active learning by agents of patterned behaviour in contrast to the Habermasian deduction of logics from theory and their generalised usage. Bourdieu uses logic-of-practice to explain stability and change: practice-based habituations and frameworks and metaphors for thinking. Bourdieu’s logic-of-practice grounds logics in situated practice, not to be confused with Gidden’s (1984) use of the term for whom logic-of-practice results in new social structures.
We conclude that conceptual development in public organisation theory often features the idea of logics: isomorphic logic, public service logic, logics in management decision taking, logics in framing the rules of the game, logic in the management of networks, service-dominant logic. How conceptually robust, grounded and evidentially-situated are these logics in public organisation research? How do different logics relate to one another? We turn now to look further inside logics from the perspective of human agency.

Agent-Centred Social Theory

Problematising logics in public organisation research and highlighting Bourdieu’s point that logics are learned, draws attention to active human agency as learners. Agency too is a contested idea: are cognition and intent essential characteristics, (b) what constitutes collective agency and (c) is agency contingent on context? Our perspective is that agency necessarily involves cognitive intent, and this precludes non-human ‘actants’ from agency, though in the special sense of distributed learning, collectives of people may be said metaphorically to possess agency.
Following Elder-Vass’s (2010) we agree that Archer’s (2003) internal conversation shaping agency and Bourdieu’s (1984) idea of habitus influencing agency are reconciled by the idea of emergence from complexity theory. This aligns with Morin’s (1959, 1982, 1986) contribution to active agency in French social theory, which can be underestimated; he spoke of recursive causality, in similar terms to Whitehead’s (1929) being and becoming: social order both creates and is created by active human agency.
Agentic acting with intent suggests intention-to-act (future) and intention-in-action (current activity). Intention therefore introduces psychological deliberation into agency, often as Elster (1979) notes from pre-commitment to particular goals citing ends-means coherence. Intention seeks control over future outcomes resulting from present behaviour; it is volition to act as Bratman (1987; 1991) says, based on cognitive reflection and/or beliefs, what Dewey calls reflective intelligence.
Since individuals are continually interpreting and responding to events and the activities of other agents, this catalyses new flows of conduct (Giddens, 1979:55) that continually emerge making human cognitive agency the micro-foundation of social research. Individual cognition and learning is then central to active agency, this the opposite of structural theory (Parsons, Althusser) which accords agency to non-cognitive structures such as bureaucracy and organisation. Similarly, we reject actor-network approaches (Latour, 1992), that attribute agency to non-human actants.
We employ Vygotsky’s (1986) social learning approach in which learning is social; featuring cognitions, relationality and emotions (especially trust); these mediate learning through the individual’s context and culture. Language, frameworks, concepts, social morès and norms influence learning. As Wertsch et al. (1995:25) says, we can never speak from nowhere. Learning cannot be reduced to bio-deterministic synaptic processing. Bernstein (2000) blends agent-centred and social learning approaches to explaining social change (see Hasan, 2001, 2005. He argues that restricted and elaborated codes of interpretation are the result of interaction between active agents’ identity and inherited cultural meanings. New social constructions, emergences that may constitute logics, can be weak or strong for Elder-Vass, yet always—as Arthur’s (2015) complexity theory suggests—arise from non-linear thinking and active processes with unforeseen results, the result of emotional attachments. Social learning aligns closely with Bourdieu’s logic-of-practice: concrete experiences and their interpretation by cognitive human agents, balance stability (morphostasis) and change (morphogenesis). Sense-making (which includes possible logics) are always provisional and transitory, since social life is always dynamically responding to the actions and ideas of other people and external events. Agentic intent then is ontologically founded on social learning, which is always relational and in arenas of complexity, continuous; context mediates without deterministically shaping learning and intent.

Context and Active Agency

Cognitive human agents have both the capability to act and the capacity for cognition. Capability allows intent to result in social effects; those intended or not (Hvinden et al. 2018). Distinctive human agency (Ci 2011) is power, since intentions always subjectively mobilises bias (Schattschneider, 1975a, 1975b). All agents operate in domains in which this subjective power is recognised as plausible (or not); contexts therefore give content (intention) and modality to agency. As Kiser (1999) argues this makes agents and their context inseparable. “Logic” becomes an accumulation of behaviour at an individual level from which the individual learns; it is not a superstructural imposition.
Agency is relational, enlivened only in social processes (Burkitt, 2016). It is in Whitehead’s (1929) terms becoming, not being: an emergence that is coproduced (Weber, 2006). The interactivity of agents creates intent not something inherent in objects (Dépelteau 2010). This perspective closely aligns with relational sociology, which focuses on processual relationships (Emirbayer and Mishe 1998; Daniels, 2001). Unlike Vandenberghe (2010), who suggests human agents can operate without prior intent, we follow Gergen (2009 and Archer (2012; 2013) who insist that agency presumes reflexivity, which by iterational morphogenesis explains how agents both produce and reproduce social structures. Social structures are important Elder-Vass (2010) argues not because they dictate logics, but rather because they mediate learning, which may become logics: social structures cannot act independently of human intent.
Elder-Vass (2010, 2007a, 2007b) points out that although at first sight (a) Archer’s (2003) emphasis on reflexivity (internal conversation) shaping agency (and creating personal and social identity), and (b) Bourdieu’s (1984) accent on habitus as socially conditioning (generative capacity to produce, reproduce, change), appear irreconcilable, the idea of emergence (from complexity theory) reconciles the two approaches. Agency itself is always emergent, always becoming. Welcoming these ideas, our view is that further steps are needed to explore how the social learning processes occur the give rise to and interpret emergences, leading us towards Vygotskian social learning.

Collective Agency?

What then of collective agency, such as Marx’s (1852) class for itself or collective unlearning in public organisations (Stenvall et al., 2018), or corporate responsibility? Law often ascribes moral responsibility to corporate bodies. However, the agency of collective bodies (state, working-class, companies) is quite different from individual agency, which presumes cognitive ability and as Arendt (1969) argued, collective actions cannot abrogate the inalienable culpability for their actions. Nor can agency be confused or conflated with finance principal-agency theory, which often ignores context and presumes rational choice (Becker, Williamson). For Perrow (1990:121) this approach is not only wrong but also dangerous. Since agency presumes learners and intent, collective agency such as learning organisations are illusory – organisations cannot learn, since only individual cognisant individuals can think.
Grounded logics are the human/social construction working on nature and in social relationships, the dialectical logics Marx developed in Capital (1993), applied historically (1852) and justified philosophically (1976), grounded in his theory of capitalism (1973) and which Engels (1859) related to dialectics of nature. Whereas some social theorists (Schatzki 2019 being an example) sayings and doings shape social change, Marx (1973) that it is not ideals (ideas ungrounded in material practice) that drive social change. Instead, humans being the only animal capable of advanced cognition, including intentionality (design) and purposive labour enhancing the productivity of nature, we use self-consciousness to create social consciousness. Shared with others and becoming collective intentionality and consciousness, social change results. Humans are capable of thought-through collective agency. It is from patterns of agency that new logics are created and in turn, individual cognitions and collective intent make use of previously formulated logics. Logics then are actively constructed, quite unlike abstracted ideas such as Kant’s imperative or Smith invisible hand.
Whereas individual consciousness is the result of cognition and affect (Vygotsky, 1986), collective consciousness is embedded from external sources. Blackmore’s (2003) memes and Durkheim’s (1893) analysis of religious show this occurring in wider society. In organisations and organising however, Wittgenstein’s follow the rules is replaced by follow the leader, since as Schattschneider (1975a, 1975b:71) says, organisations are the mobilisation of bias they necessarily privilege certain outcomes. Collectivities of people in organisations instead of following an ideology, and ideal in Ilyenkov’s (2008) terms, require a dynamic narrative connecting problem and solution, creating organic solidarity: collective consciousness in organisations is necessarily highly situated and, where leadership is effective, is guided towards understanding the germ-cell or essence of the problem, recognising contradictions in the current state-of-affairs, and takes collective active to achieve what the leader has explained as a preferred solution (Prilleltensky (1997:525). Individuals still must make sense of the leader’s narrative; often this is helped by framing, frameworks, metaphors and language supplied by the leader. Part of the leader’s role in ecosystems is legitimising the other agents in the ecosystem, with whom the organisation’s members must work in order to deliver the preferred solution. For Blunden (2015) effective project work in organisations relies on leadership building this collective consciousness. Such leaders will combine vision with the leadership, management and administrative competences to which Hartley and Allison (2000) refer. Creating collective consciousness in a public or other organisation, requires a leader able to make sense of problem–solution in context and culture and to marshal the collective into activity.
One of the more contentious results of what Bernstein (2000) terms the cultural turn in social theory, is the attribution of agency to culture. As Harvey (1982) and others make clear, scaling between levels of analysis only makes sense if not employed as a deterministic hierarchy of simplified causalities from the general to the particular.

Socio-Cultural Theory

Learning and deploying new knowledge is then an essential aspect of active agency: learning patterns of activity from logic-of-practice creates new bottom-up governances and learning from user feedback helps personalise the design and delivery of local public services. How then does this occur? Figure 1 is a simplified exposition of how social learning occurs using Vygotsky’s (1986; 1997) perspective and drawing on the work of Engeström et al., (1999), Nardi (1996) and Illeris (2004). Individual thinking is shaped by logics and in distribution new logics are formulated, in turn influenced by context and culture. Arrows 1, 2 and 3 indicate these interactions constituting the activity centre in the middle of Fig. 1 illustrating how logics influences learning and in turn by learning and patterned practice, new logics are created. A key point is the sense-making by cognitive individuals references their emotional attachments both to old ways-of-working and to a vision of how new services and governances might operate drawing on heuristics (thinking frameworks) evolved from formal education and in practice. As Vygotsky (1986:282) says, [Thought] is not born of other thoughts. Thought has its origins in the motivating sphere of consciousness, a sphere that includes our inclinations and needs, our interests and impulses, and our affect and emotions Figs. 2 3.
Individual learning (top-left) is distributed during organising service delivery (top-right). All learning occurs in a specific context (bottom-left) meaning ‘hard’ rules and norms such as budgets, regulations, ethical standards and (bottom-right) ‘soft’ cultural norms such as general social culture, occupational culture. While taking account of ‘objective’ facts, the individual learning is non-rational.
Trust is an especially important emotion in individual learning and its distribution for PM since the services target vulnerable people reliant on trust and trust accompanies representatives between sets of professionals. As Weibel and Six (2013) argue, this willing acceptance of vulnerability between agents in turn presupposes relatedness between agents, competence and autonomy. Trust and control are in once sense opposites and in another complementary. More trust in a service system means less need for formal management structures and oversight accountability. When trouble occurs Six (2005) notes, trust is either dissipated or strengthened.
Social learning then is relational and offers a way of improving Elder-Vass’s position by explaining how agent learning reframes and reformulates logics in situated theorisations of public service dynamics.

Logics in Public Service Organisation Research

Taking two oft-cited uses of logics in public organisation research as examples, here we consider how far they are grounded in learning by active agents.
We have chosen (a) Vargo and Lusch’s (2004, 2007, 2008 and 2017) service-dominant logic and (b) Kooiman (2003); and Klijn and Koppenjan’s (2014) management of networks. We choose Vargo and Lusch and Kooiman and Klijn because they will be familiar to readers, and each apply logics at the level of organisations delivering services. The choices are for illustrative purposes; we are not in any way suggesting that these pieces of research are other than valuable. In each case, we present a table of how logics are referenced in these two bodies of research relative to social learning by active agent in logic-of-practice.

Service-Dominant Logic and Logic Evaluation

Vargo and Lusch (2004, 2007, 2008, 2017) offer an integrated marketing perspective on services, arguing that value (in use) is co-created by service providers and users; focusing on private services little mention is made of public services. They argue that a goods-dominant logic (GDL, featuring tangible goods, a supply-side mindset and objective success criteria) is being superseded by a SDL, which concentrates on intangible services, a customer-focused mindset and subjective success criteria: goods are a distribution mechanism for services. Our focus here is on the use Vargo and Lusch make of logics and the extent to which the logics are grounded in practice and agent learning.
Using Lusch and Vargo (2014), a 224-page exposition of SDL, Table 1 summarises the stance taken in relations to factors constituting grounded logics. In this welcome exhortation to adopt customer-focused activity, non-exchange (public and some 3S) people and public organisations are seldom mentioned. New service dominant logics arise in abstract exchange relationships. Few individual service providers or people are mentioned; the logics are derived from market exchange. SDL is presented as a new paradigm evolving from firms’ exchange activity, without any reference to the people constituting the firms. For example, new knowledge arises from exchange, without mention of learning, cognition, affectations. The SDL world is populated by firms exchanging services with other firms and customers, none of which reference in any detailed way the context and culture in which the exchanges occur. SDL is a switch from GDL the processes of which do not feature human agentic involvement.
Table 1
Logics in service-dominant logic (page references from Lusch and Vargo 2014)
Comments evaluating service-dominant logic in relation to Table-1 framework
Individual learning
  
 
Individual cognitions
(113) actor-centricity; actors are economic exchange units
 
Emotional attachments
(114) actors not rational; (117) free agents
 
Affectations
(77) human actors are more effectual than rational
 
Ways of working
(94) resource integration enhances value
 
Learning style
(146) Psychic benefits: customers enjoy co-producing; (150) adaptive competence important; (152) learning from exchange (164) self-adjusting service ecosystems
 
Heritage knowledge
(77) knowledge dynamically changing
 
User involvement in services
(15) Customers always co-producers of value
 
Diversity of prevailing logics
Only GDL and SDL
Organising services
  
 
Legitimacy/acceptance of logics and heuristics
(10) actor to actor relationships,
 
Relationships between all agents
(6) Firm-centric unit of analysis
(73 relational to customers (long-term relationship)
  
 
Interplay between services and structures
(24) service ecosystem, multi-layered, nested
 
Control/trust: abilities to deliver and innovate
(166) institutional governance of markets differs between countries
 
Opportunities for distributing learning
(165) knowledge distributed by networks
 
Services as an (integrated) system (overall-logics)
(10) common purpose of resource integration and service-for-service exchange
Context
  
 
Control and trust interplay
(103) actor-to-actor exchange key dynamic
 
Embedded knowledge in structures and services
(87) contextual contingency, especially resources
 
Standards and regulations and prevailing logics
(139) normalising practice created new standards
 
Resource enablers and constraints
(120) resources constrain, SDL enables
 
Formal and informal governances
(23) value in context, markets, structuration
 
Influence of external logics
(171) Macro, meso micro institutions and resource integrators
Culture
  
 
Logics: professional, occupational & wide culture
(166) customer cultures vary
 
Open to new ideas, ways-of-working & logics
(130) resource integration key dynamic
 
Acceptance of bottom-up change
(168) Bottom-up new normalising from exchange
 
Competitive logics
(Cpt-4) GDL is competitor logic
Learned logics
SDL catalyses integration and collaboration
 
Our point is this: while Lusch and Vargo refer often to being actor-centric, there are few people in their exposition of logics and almost no public sector. The logics arise from market exchange between economic units (firms) within ecosystems and institutions envisaged from a market exchange perspective. There is no human thinking, feeling, or (human) relations agency. Agency is ascribed to inanimate entities: abstracted customers and firms. Although the services ecosystems self-adjust, they appear to do so without human decisions, responses, creativities. The only practice referenced are those of resource integration and market exchange; not real people, using real services. No competitive or conflicting logics exist, apart from GDL. This new SDL paradigm exists without reference to particular and situated contexts and cultures. SDL is a metaphysic, a belief system not grounded in practice or reality, not subject to verification or disproof. The logic is without reference to human intervention and can only be categorised as deterministic.

Network of Management Governances and Logic Evaluation

Kooiman’s 249-page exposition (2003) and later work including Klijn (2008) and Klijn and Koppenjan (2014) presents a logic for governance analysis based on management of networks, used in a 427-page study of fisheries governance (2005). Kooiman and Bavink, (2013) sets out to explain how interdependency and relationships between agencies can best operate as society becomes more complex, dynamic and diverse. Table 2 summarises the stance taken by network management theorists towards grounding logics in practice and learning.
Table 2
Logics network management of governances
taken from Kooiman (2003); Klijn (2008) and Klijn and Koppenjan (2014)
Comments evaluating network management of governance logic in relation to Table-1 framework
Individual learning
  
 
Individual cognitions
Individuals make only rational decisions: rationality as much as instrumental rationality
 
Emotional attachments
Rational decisions exclude emotions
 
Affectations
Affect does not feature in rational agency
 
Ways of working
Management of network is by a central Director (usually the Government)
 
Learning style
Central Director filters learning: learning mentioned but not shown as central to logics
 
Heritage knowledge
Advocacy coalitions in networks cite knowledge in arguments
 
User involvement in services
Networks are composed of providers; limited if any user involvement
 
Diversity of prevailing logics
Task of Central Director is giving coherence to network goals and processes
Organising services
  
 
Legitimacy/acceptance of logics and heuristics
Legitimacy is successful fusion of network with new public management adoption
 
Relationships between all agents
Unit of analysis are organisations acting in networks not individual humans
 
Interplay between services and structures
Networks communications facilitate isomorphic change
 
Control/trust: abilities to deliver and innovate
Focus on state-level policy/actions; Central Director; regimes governing relationships (e.g. Public Private Partnerships) work best with trust
 
Opportunities for distributing learning
A pragmatic approach, governances allow Central Director to impose solutions
 
Services as an (integrated) system (overall-logics)
Adoption of NPM a desirable outcome
Context
  
 
Control and trust interplay
Network goal is to build trust in network by actors
 
Embedded knowledge in structures and services
While technical knowledge influences structures, other relevant knowledge results from rational debate
 
Standards and regulations and prevailing logics
Networks comply with formal knowledge standards
 
Resource enablers and constraints
Central Director has most resources; uses power to arrange problem solving and give voice to under-represented actors
 
Formal and informal governances
Chains of action-reaction occur, Central Director guides these towards appropriate structures and solutions
Informal governances help formal governances to deliver solutions
  
 
Influence of external logics
Wide variety of external governances and logics with which network governances interact
Culture
  
 
Logics: professional, occupational & wide culture
Culture not important to analysing change,
Culture may introduce problematic inconsistencies
  
 
Open to new ideas, ways-of-working & logics
Openness defined by Central Director
 
Acceptance of bottom-up change
If Central Director judge it valid
 
Competitive logics
Alternative networks unlikely if Central Director brings/control critical resources
Learned logics
Network participants learn to comply with goals and processes distilled by Central Director
 
For Kooiman networks are the preferred structure to solve problems and a Central-Controller led governance manages the network. Central Controllers, usually Government, bring resources to problem-solving; networks are characterised by rational-cognitive agency and reference formal knowledge in decision taking. NPM efficiency is a desirable goal of the networks. Networks form governance hierarchies with first-order governance (day-to-day), institutional arrangements (second order) and (third order) meta-governance (similar to Habermas’ communicative rationality. Network governance is appropriate to policy networking, inter-organisational delivery of service and policy implementation: it is not confined to second-order policy making. The logic in network management then is compliance with the preferences of the Central Controller; often the targets and processes associated with new public management.
To assess the implications of Table 2 in steps. Kooiman and his colleagues argue that governances are best analysed and constructed as networks, that networks are best centrally directed, network participants ought to act and think rationally, the possessing resources (power) gives legitimacy to network central directors and that these logics apply whatever the context and culture.
Network management as a logic is not grounded in active agency; it is not derived from lessons learned by cognitive-emotional humans. The approach appears to be a quirky ideal type justifying the adopting of new public management and legitimating the power of central Government in public service design and delivery.

Discussion and Conclusions

Tables 1 and 2 illustrate little evidence of learning by active agents and little evidence of grounding their prescribed logics in practice. Why is this absence of social learning in SDL and the Rotterdam group’s network management approach important? The answer is that social research bereft of cognisant people is questionable: the social constructions resulting from such research are from inside the mind of the researchers not logic-of-practice.
It is of course possible to argue that logics are an implicit or sub-conscious aspect of agent behaviour. None of the theorists mentioned take this position. Assuming an unverifiable set of beliefs would open new methodological cans of worms. Does this invalidate the approaches suggested by SDL and network management? Not necessarily, however, it makes it important to know the epistemic stance of the researchers.
Both Lusch and Vargo and Kooiman and his colleagues are suggesting that there are alternative mindsets to (for example) market transactionality (price) or hierarchy (power). Both sets of researchers are proposing new principles to guide thinking and action. Our central point is that each offer a play without actors, a world without people; principles decided deductively not grounded, ways of operating where the key units of analysis are not cognitive-emotional persons, but instead firms/exchanges (SDL) or organisations in networks.
Both SDL and network management are logics oft cited in public organisation research. Llewelyn (2003) argued that there are five types of theorising available to qualitative researchers: (a) metaphors; (b) differentiation; (c) conceptualisation; (d) context-bound theorising of settings and (e) context-free ‘grand’ theorizing. Both SDL and network management are context-free theorising: meta-narratives, in each case produced from deep conceptual reflection on enduring social relationships and causalities of how structures and agency interact. The fact that such theorisations are not derived from empirically substantiated agent learning that grounds logics in practice, does not in itself deprive them of usefulness.
Nonetheless, deduced theorisation should be acknowledged, and the assumptions laid bare; so that when applied to particular types of human agency or situated contexts and cultures, it is clear what evidence from structures and agency are appropriate for researchers using these approaches to seek. If there are contexts and cultures to which SDL and network management do not apply, then this too should be acknowledged to avoid using the approaches to inappropriately frame research problems and/or embed assumptions in empirical work unknowingly. This is especially important for public organisation research which is international in nature, transgressive of contexts and cultures and needs to know if conceptual tools are proposed as universally applicable or if of limited generalisability, the nature of the limitations. Our own view is that the logics in SDL is a metaphysic and network management epistemologically flawed, given its assumptions of rationality and privileging of power. Neither approach is universally applicable—contexts and cultures vary considerably.
General theories are stronger on explanation (attributed causality, i.e. why) and weaker on understanding (i.e. what—identifying the existence of outcomes predicted by the theory); since social research phenomena are constructions. This can lead to confusing the map with the terrain i.e. finding what one sets out looking for, making theory falsification impossible. This of course is the great advantage of grounding social research by investigating agent interpretations and actions: instead of beginning with a theory and seeking evidence of its usefulness. As Glaser and Strauss (1967:2) propose grounded theory discovers theory from systematic data. Groundedness itself being a metaphor for linking to a feedback loop, such as ethnographic studies or qualitative interviews producing case studies. For Archer (2000) grasping both agency and structures is essential to explaining social activity: neither SDL nor network management do this.
We conclude that some researchers continue to find Lusch and Vargo’s SDL and Kooiman’s network management logics, or theories, useful. Their use however should be constrained by a clear understanding of how the key concepts relate to the particular context and culture being studied. Further, researchers should note that in focus on logics comes at the cost of not focusing on human agency – a controversial choice in public management research. As Fig. 1 illustrates use of logics is not passive, from using logics new logics emerge addressing contradictions and conflicts in the previous patterns of logics, as they apply to current problems.
For public organisation managers the clear implication of this research is to avoid off-the-shelf, transformative, paradigm-switching new tools. There is no alternative but deeply investigating problems in situation, digging to identify the germ-cell essence of any problem and to propose solutions accordingly. Public manager should always to wary of universal tools or solutions and instead be unafraid to conclude that their organisation, their problem requires tools of analysis and solutions uniquely suiting their organisation and its capabilities. Our contribution revolves around viewing logics not as passive ‘ideas’ isolated from practice, but instead as ‘actively’ helping to socially construct what current practice is and thereby create new logics. In short, logics occupy a dialectical place in learning and problem solving and are not static nor fixed.
Open AccessThis article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article's Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article's Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://​creativecommons.​org/​licenses/​by/​4.​0/​.

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Archer, M. (2003). Structure, agency and the internal conversation. CUP.CrossRef Archer, M. (2003). Structure, agency and the internal conversation. CUP.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Arendt, H. (1951). The origins of totalitarianism. Harvest Books. Arendt, H. (1951). The origins of totalitarianism. Harvest Books.
Zurück zum Zitat Arendt, H. (1958). The human condition. The University of Chicago Press. Arendt, H. (1958). The human condition. The University of Chicago Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Arendt, H. (1969). On violence. Harvest/HBJ. Arendt, H. (1969). On violence. Harvest/HBJ.
Zurück zum Zitat Berg, L. N., Puusa, A., Pulkkinen, K., & Geschwind, L. (2017). Managers’ identities: Solid or affected by changes in institutional logics and organisational amendments? Scandinavian Journal of Public Administration, 21(1), 81–101. Berg, L. N., Puusa, A., Pulkkinen, K., & Geschwind, L. (2017). Managers’ identities: Solid or affected by changes in institutional logics and organisational amendments? Scandinavian Journal of Public Administration, 21(1), 81–101.
Zurück zum Zitat Berman, E. P. (2012). Explaining the move toward the market in US academic science: How institutional logics can change without institutional entrepreneurs. Theory and Society, 41(3), 261–299.CrossRef Berman, E. P. (2012). Explaining the move toward the market in US academic science: How institutional logics can change without institutional entrepreneurs. Theory and Society, 41(3), 261–299.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Bernstein, B. (2000). Pedagogy, symbolic control and identity: Theory, research critique, Rowman and Littlefield, Lanham. Bernstein, B. (2000). Pedagogy, symbolic control and identity: Theory, research critique, Rowman and Littlefield, Lanham.
Zurück zum Zitat Bjerregaard, T. (2011). Co-existing institutional logics and agency among top-level public servants: A praxeological approach. Journal of Management & Organisation, 17(2), 194–209.CrossRef Bjerregaard, T. (2011). Co-existing institutional logics and agency among top-level public servants: A praxeological approach. Journal of Management & Organisation, 17(2), 194–209.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Blackmore, S. (2003). Consciousness: An Introduction. Hodder & Stoughton. Blackmore, S. (2003). Consciousness: An Introduction. Hodder & Stoughton.
Zurück zum Zitat Blunden, A. (Ed.). (2015). Collaborative Projects – An Interdisciplinary Study. Haymarket. Blunden, A. (Ed.). (2015). Collaborative Projects – An Interdisciplinary Study. Haymarket.
Zurück zum Zitat Bright, L. (2021). Why does PSM lead to higher work stress? Exploring the Role that Organizational Identity Theory has on the Relationship between Public Service Motivation and External-Related Stress among Federal Government Employees, Public Organization Review, https://doi.org/10.1007/s11115-021-00546-0 Bright, L. (2021). Why does PSM lead to higher work stress? Exploring the Role that Organizational Identity Theory has on the Relationship between Public Service Motivation and External-Related Stress among Federal Government Employees, Public Organization Review, https://​doi.​org/​10.​1007/​s11115-021-00546-0
Zurück zum Zitat Burkitt, I. (2016). Relational agency: Relational sociology, agency and interaction. European Journal of Social Theory, 19(3), 322–339. Burkitt, I. (2016). Relational agency: Relational sociology, agency and interaction. European Journal of Social Theory, 19(3), 322–339.
Zurück zum Zitat Chomsky, N. (1969). Objectivity and liberal scholarship, in American Power and the New Mandarins. Penguin. Chomsky, N. (1969). Objectivity and liberal scholarship, in American Power and the New Mandarins. Penguin.
Zurück zum Zitat Daniels, H. (2001). Vygotsky and pedagogy, Routledge-Falmer, Abingdon. Daniels, H. (2001). Vygotsky and pedagogy, Routledge-Falmer, Abingdon.
Zurück zum Zitat Dépelteau, F. (2010). Relational thinking in sociology: Relevance, concurrence and dissonance, in Hyman, J., & Steward, H. (2010). Agency and Action, CUP, Cambridge. Dépelteau, F. (2010). Relational thinking in sociology: Relevance, concurrence and dissonance, in Hyman, J., & Steward, H. (2010). Agency and Action, CUP, Cambridge.
Zurück zum Zitat Dewey, J. (1938). Logic: The theory of inquiry. Holt. Dewey, J. (1938). Logic: The theory of inquiry. Holt.
Zurück zum Zitat DiMaggio, P. J., & Powell, W. W. (1983). The iron cage revisited: Institutional isomorphism and collective rationality in organizational fields. American Sociological Review, 48, 147–160.CrossRef DiMaggio, P. J., & Powell, W. W. (1983). The iron cage revisited: Institutional isomorphism and collective rationality in organizational fields. American Sociological Review, 48, 147–160.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Douglas, M. (1987). How Institutions Think. Routledge & Kegan Paul. Douglas, M. (1987). How Institutions Think. Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Zurück zum Zitat Dunn, M. B., & Jones, C. (2010). Institutional logics and institutional pluralism: The contestation of care and science logics in medical education. Administrative Science Quarterly, 55(1), 114–149.CrossRef Dunn, M. B., & Jones, C. (2010). Institutional logics and institutional pluralism: The contestation of care and science logics in medical education. Administrative Science Quarterly, 55(1), 114–149.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Durkheim, E. (1893). 1984. The Division of Labour in Society. Durkheim, E. (1893). 1984. The Division of Labour in Society.
Zurück zum Zitat Elder-Vass, D. (2007a). Social structure and social relations. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 37(4), 466–477.CrossRef Elder-Vass, D. (2007a). Social structure and social relations. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 37(4), 466–477.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Elder-Vass, D. (2007b). Reconciling Archer and Bourdieu in an Emergentist Theory of Action. Sociological Theory, 25(4), 325–346.CrossRef Elder-Vass, D. (2007b). Reconciling Archer and Bourdieu in an Emergentist Theory of Action. Sociological Theory, 25(4), 325–346.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Elster, Jon (ed) (1979). Ulysses and the Sirens: Studies in Rationality and Irrationality. Editions De La Maison des Sciences De L'Homme. Elster, Jon (ed) (1979). Ulysses and the Sirens: Studies in Rationality and Irrationality. Editions De La Maison des Sciences De L'Homme.
Zurück zum Zitat Engeström, Y. (1996). Developmental studies of work as a test bench of activity theory: the case of primary care medical practice, Chaiklin, S. and Lave, J. (Eds.), (1996) Understanding practice: perspectives on activity and context, CUP, Cambridge, Ch. 3. Engeström, Y. (1996). Developmental studies of work as a test bench of activity theory: the case of primary care medical practice, Chaiklin, S. and Lave, J. (Eds.), (1996) Understanding practice: perspectives on activity and context, CUP, Cambridge, Ch. 3.
Zurück zum Zitat Engeström, Y., Miettinen, R., & Punamaki, R. L. (1999). Perspectives on activity theory. CUP.CrossRef Engeström, Y., Miettinen, R., & Punamaki, R. L. (1999). Perspectives on activity theory. CUP.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Epstein, R. (1995). The semantic foundations of logic. Oxford University Press. Epstein, R. (1995). The semantic foundations of logic. Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Fleck, L. (1979). The genesis and development of scientific fact. University of Chicago Press. Fleck, L. (1979). The genesis and development of scientific fact. University of Chicago Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Freidson, E. (2001). Professionalism: The third logic. Polity Press. Freidson, E. (2001). Professionalism: The third logic. Polity Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Friedland, R., & Alford, R. R. (1991). ‘Bringing society back in: symbols, practices, and institutionalcontradictions’. In Powell, W. W. & DiMaggio, P. J. (Eds), The New Institutionalism in OrganizationalAnalysis. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 232–66. Friedland, R., & Alford, R. R. (1991). ‘Bringing society back in: symbols, practices, and institutionalcontradictions’. In Powell, W. W. & DiMaggio, P. J. (Eds), The New Institutionalism in OrganizationalAnalysis. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 232–66.
Zurück zum Zitat Giddens, A. (1979). Central problems in social theory: Action, structure and contradiction in social analysis, University of California Press, CA. Giddens, A. (1979). Central problems in social theory: Action, structure and contradiction in social analysis, University of California Press, CA.
Zurück zum Zitat Giddens, A. (1984). The constitution of society. CUP. Giddens, A. (1984). The constitution of society. CUP.
Zurück zum Zitat Glaser, B. G., & Strauss, A. L. (1967). The discovery of grounded theory. Aldine Publishing. Glaser, B. G., & Strauss, A. L. (1967). The discovery of grounded theory. Aldine Publishing.
Zurück zum Zitat Hartley, J., & Allison, M. (2000). The role of leadership in modernisation and improvement of public service. Public Money and Management, 20(2), 35–40.CrossRef Hartley, J., & Allison, M. (2000). The role of leadership in modernisation and improvement of public service. Public Money and Management, 20(2), 35–40.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Harvey, D. (1982). The limits to capital. Chicago University Press. Harvey, D. (1982). The limits to capital. Chicago University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Hasan, R. (2001). Understanding Talk: Directions from Bernstein’s Sociology. International Journal of Social Research Methodology, 4(1), 5–9.CrossRef Hasan, R. (2001). Understanding Talk: Directions from Bernstein’s Sociology. International Journal of Social Research Methodology, 4(1), 5–9.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Hasan, R. (2005). Semiotic mediation, language and society: three exotripic theories: Vygotsky, Halliday and Bernstein, in Webster JJ (Ed.), Language, society and consciousness, Equinox, London. Hasan, R. (2005). Semiotic mediation, language and society: three exotripic theories: Vygotsky, Halliday and Bernstein, in Webster JJ (Ed.), Language, society and consciousness, Equinox, London.
Zurück zum Zitat Hvinden, B., & Halvorsen, R. (2018). Mediating Agency and Structure in Sociology: What Role for Conversion Factors? Critical Sociology, 44(6), 865–881.CrossRef Hvinden, B., & Halvorsen, R. (2018). Mediating Agency and Structure in Sociology: What Role for Conversion Factors? Critical Sociology, 44(6), 865–881.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Illeris, K. (2004). Learning in working life. Roskilde University Press. Illeris, K. (2004). Learning in working life. Roskilde University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Ilyenkov, E. V. (2008). Dialectical logic – Essays on its history and theory. Aakar Books. Ilyenkov, E. V. (2008). Dialectical logic – Essays on its history and theory. Aakar Books.
Zurück zum Zitat Jackall, R. (1988). Moral mazes: The world of corporate managers. Oxford University Press. Jackall, R. (1988). Moral mazes: The world of corporate managers. Oxford University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Jacobsen, D. I. (2021). Motivational differences? Comparing private, public and hybrid organizations. Public Organization Review, 21(3), 561–575. Jacobsen, D. I. (2021). Motivational differences? Comparing private, public and hybrid organizations. Public Organization Review, 21(3), 561–575.
Zurück zum Zitat Janik, A., & Toulmin, S. (1996). Wittgenstein’s Vienna. Elephant Paperback. Janik, A., & Toulmin, S. (1996). Wittgenstein’s Vienna. Elephant Paperback.
Zurück zum Zitat Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1982). Judgement under uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases, CUP, Cambridge. Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1982). Judgement under uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases, CUP, Cambridge.
Zurück zum Zitat Kiser, E. (1999). Comparing varieties of agency theory in economics, political science and sociology: An illustration from state policy implementation. Sociological Theory, 17(2), 146–170.CrossRef Kiser, E. (1999). Comparing varieties of agency theory in economics, political science and sociology: An illustration from state policy implementation. Sociological Theory, 17(2), 146–170.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Klijn, E. H. (2008). Complexity theory and public administration: What’s new? Public Management Review, 10(3), 299–317.CrossRef Klijn, E. H. (2008). Complexity theory and public administration: What’s new? Public Management Review, 10(3), 299–317.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Klijn, E. H., & Koppenjan, J. F. M. (2014). Complexity in governance network theory. Complexity, Governance & Networks, 1(1), 61–70.CrossRef Klijn, E. H., & Koppenjan, J. F. M. (2014). Complexity in governance network theory. Complexity, Governance & Networks, 1(1), 61–70.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Klijn, E. H., Sierra, V., Ysa, T., Berman, E., Edelenbos, J., & Chen, D. Y. (2016). The influence of trust on network performance in Taiwan, Spain, and the Netherlands: A cross-country comparison. International Public Management Journal, 19(1), 111–139. Klijn, E. H., Sierra, V., Ysa, T., Berman, E., Edelenbos, J., & Chen, D. Y. (2016). The influence of trust on network performance in Taiwan, Spain, and the Netherlands: A cross-country comparison. International Public Management Journal, 19(1), 111–139.
Zurück zum Zitat Kooiman, J., & Bavinck, M. (2013). Theorizing governability–The interactive governance perspective. In Governability of fisheries and aquaculture (pp. 9–30). Springer, Dordrecht. Kooiman, J., & Bavinck, M. (2013). Theorizing governability–The interactive governance perspective. In Governability of fisheries and aquaculture (pp. 9–30). Springer, Dordrecht.
Zurück zum Zitat Kooiman, J., Bavvinck, M., Jentoft, S., & Pullin, R. (2005). Fish for life: Interactive governance for fisheries. Amsterdam University Press.CrossRef Kooiman, J., Bavvinck, M., Jentoft, S., & Pullin, R. (2005). Fish for life: Interactive governance for fisheries. Amsterdam University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Latour, B. (1992). “Where are the missing masses? The sociology of a few mundane artefacts,” in Bijker WE & Law J (Eds.), (1992). Shaping Technology/Building Society, MIT, London, pg. 225 - 258. Latour, B. (1992). “Where are the missing masses? The sociology of a few mundane artefacts,” in Bijker WE & Law J (Eds.), (1992). Shaping Technology/Building Society, MIT, London, pg. 225 - 258.
Zurück zum Zitat Lipsky, M. (1980). Street-level Bureaucracy: Dilemmas of the individual in Public Services. Sage. Lipsky, M. (1980). Street-level Bureaucracy: Dilemmas of the individual in Public Services. Sage.
Zurück zum Zitat Llewelyn, S. (2003). What counts as theory in qualitative management and accounting research? Accounting, Auditing & Accountability Journal, 16(4), 662–708.CrossRef Llewelyn, S. (2003). What counts as theory in qualitative management and accounting research? Accounting, Auditing & Accountability Journal, 16(4), 662–708.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Lopes, T. S. A., & Alves, H. (2020). Coproduction and cocreation in public care services: a systematic review. International Journal of Public Sector Management. Lopes, T. S. A., & Alves, H. (2020). Coproduction and cocreation in public care services: a systematic review. International Journal of Public Sector Management.
Zurück zum Zitat Lounsbury, M. (2007). A tale of two cities: Competing logics and practice variation in the profssionalising of mutual funds. Academy of Management Journal, 50(2), 289–307.CrossRef Lounsbury, M. (2007). A tale of two cities: Competing logics and practice variation in the profssionalising of mutual funds. Academy of Management Journal, 50(2), 289–307.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Lusch, R. F., & Vargo, S. L. (2014). Service-dominant logic: Premises, perspectives, possibilities. Cambridge University Press. Lusch, R. F., & Vargo, S. L. (2014). Service-dominant logic: Premises, perspectives, possibilities. Cambridge University Press.
Zurück zum Zitat March, J. G., & Olsen, J. P. (1983). Organizing political life. What administrative reorganization tells us about government? American Political Science Review, 77(2), 281–297. March, J. G., & Olsen, J. P. (1983). Organizing political life. What administrative reorganization tells us about government? American Political Science Review, 77(2), 281–297.
Zurück zum Zitat March, J. G., & Olsen, J. P. (1989). Rediscovering Institutions. New York: Free Press. March, J. G., & Olsen, J. P.  (1989). Rediscovering Institutions. New York: Free Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Marx, K. (1852) (1967). The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte, Progress Publishing, Moscow. Marx, K. (1852) (1967). The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte, Progress Publishing, Moscow.
Zurück zum Zitat Marx K, 1993, Capital: A Critique of Political Economy, (Vol. 1), Penguin Books, London. Marx K, 1993, Capital: A Critique of Political Economy, (Vol. 1), Penguin Books, London.
Zurück zum Zitat Marx K, 1976, The German Ideology. MECW, Vol. 5. Progress Publishers, Moscow (pages 19–539). Marx K, 1976, The German Ideology. MECW, Vol. 5. Progress Publishers, Moscow (pages 19–539).
Zurück zum Zitat Marx, K. (1973). Grundrisse. Pelican. Marx, K. (1973). Grundrisse. Pelican.
Zurück zum Zitat Morin, E. (1959) (2004 Edition). Autocritique, Seuil, Paris. Morin, E. (1959) (2004 Edition). Autocritique, Seuil, Paris.
Zurück zum Zitat Morin, E. (1982). The Stars. University of Minnesota Press. Morin, E. (1982). The Stars. University of Minnesota Press.
Zurück zum Zitat Morin, E. (1986) (1992 Edition). Method – Towards a Study of nature, Peter Lang, NY. Morin, E. (1986) (1992 Edition). Method – Towards a Study of nature, Peter Lang, NY.
Zurück zum Zitat Nardi, B.A. (Ed.), (1996). Context and consciousness, MIT, Mass. Nardi, B.A. (Ed.), (1996). Context and consciousness, MIT, Mass.
Zurück zum Zitat Ngoye, B., Sierra, V., & Ysa, T. (2019). Assessing performance-use preferences through an institutional logics lens. International Journal of Public Sector Management. Ngoye, B., Sierra, V., & Ysa, T. (2019). Assessing performance-use preferences through an institutional logics lens. International Journal of Public Sector Management.
Zurück zum Zitat Normann, R. (2002). Services Management, Chichester: Wiley. Normann, R. (2002). Services Management, Chichester: Wiley.
Zurück zum Zitat Olson, M. (1970). The logic of Collective Action. Schocken Books. Olson, M. (1970). The logic of Collective Action. Schocken Books.
Zurück zum Zitat Osborne, S. P. (2017). from public service dominant logic to public service logic: Are public service organisations capable of co-creation and coproduction? Public Management Review, 20(2), 225–231.CrossRef Osborne, S. P. (2017). from public service dominant logic to public service logic: Are public service organisations capable of co-creation and coproduction? Public Management Review, 20(2), 225–231.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Perrow, C. (1990). Economic Theories of Organization. In: Sharon, Z. & Paul, D. (Eds) Structures of Capital, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 121–152. Perrow, C. (1990). Economic Theories of Organization. In: Sharon, Z. & Paul, D. (Eds) Structures of Capital, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 121–152.
Zurück zum Zitat Popper, K. (2007). Situational logic in social science inquiry: From economics to criminology The. Review of Austrian Economics, 20(1), 25–41.CrossRef Popper, K. (2007). Situational logic in social science inquiry: From economics to criminology The. Review of Austrian Economics, 20(1), 25–41.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Prilleltensky, I. (1997). Values, assumptions, and practices: Assessing the moral implications of psychological discourse and action. American Psychologist, 52, 517–535.CrossRef Prilleltensky, I. (1997). Values, assumptions, and practices: Assessing the moral implications of psychological discourse and action. American Psychologist, 52, 517–535.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Schattschneider EE, 1975, The Semisovereign People: A realist's view of democracy in America, Dryden, Illinois. Schattschneider EE, 1975, The Semisovereign People: A realist's view of democracy in America, Dryden, Illinois.
Zurück zum Zitat Schattschneider, E.E. (1975). The Semisovereign People: A realist's view of democracy in America, Dryden, Illinois. Schattschneider, E.E. (1975). The Semisovereign People: A realist's view of democracy in America, Dryden, Illinois.
Zurück zum Zitat Scott, R. W. (2008). Institutions and organizations. Sage. Scott, R. W. (2008). Institutions and organizations. Sage.
Zurück zum Zitat Selznick, P. (1948). Foundations of the theory of organization. American Sociological Review, 13(1), 25–35. Selznick, P. (1948). Foundations of the theory of organization. American Sociological Review, 13(1), 25–35.
Zurück zum Zitat Selznick, P. (1957). Leadership in administration. Harper & Row. Selznick, P. (1957). Leadership in administration. Harper & Row.
Zurück zum Zitat Stenvall, J., Kinder, T., & Kuoppakangas, P. (2018). Unlearning and public services – a case study with Vygotskian approach. Journal of Adult and Continuing Education, 24(2), 188–207.CrossRef Stenvall, J., Kinder, T., & Kuoppakangas, P. (2018). Unlearning and public services – a case study with Vygotskian approach. Journal of Adult and Continuing Education, 24(2), 188–207.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Thornton, P., & Ocasio, W. (1999). Institutional logics and the historical contingency of power in organizations: Executive succession in the higher education publishing industry, 1958–1990. American Journal of Sociology, 105(3), 801–843.CrossRef Thornton, P., & Ocasio, W. (1999). Institutional logics and the historical contingency of power in organizations: Executive succession in the higher education publishing industry, 1958–1990. American Journal of Sociology, 105(3), 801–843.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Thornton, P.H., & Ocasio, W. (2017). Institutional logics, in Greenwood R, Oliver C, Lawrence TB and Meyer RE, (Eds.), The Sage Handbook of Organisational Institutionalism, Chapter-19. Thornton, P.H., & Ocasio, W. (2017). Institutional logics, in Greenwood R, Oliver C, Lawrence TB and Meyer RE, (Eds.), The Sage Handbook of Organisational Institutionalism, Chapter-19.
Zurück zum Zitat Thornton, P. H., Ocasio, W., & Lounsbury, M. (2015). The institutional logics perspective. Wiley. Thornton, P. H., Ocasio, W., & Lounsbury, M. (2015). The institutional logics perspective. Wiley.
Zurück zum Zitat Toulmin, S. E. (2003b). The uses of argument. Cambridge University Press.CrossRef Toulmin, S. E. (2003b). The uses of argument. Cambridge University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat van Benthem, J., & Pacuit, E. (2010). Temporal Logics of Agency. Journal of Logic, Language and Information, 19(4), 389–393.CrossRef van Benthem, J., & Pacuit, E. (2010). Temporal Logics of Agency. Journal of Logic, Language and Information, 19(4), 389–393.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Vargo, S.L., & Lusch, R.F. (2004). Evolving to a new dominant logic for marketing, Journal of Marketing, 68, January 1–17. Vargo, S.L., & Lusch, R.F. (2004). Evolving to a new dominant logic for marketing, Journal of Marketing, 68, January 1–17.
Zurück zum Zitat Vargo, S. L., & Lusch, R. F. (2007). Service-dominant logic: Continuing the evolution. Journal of Academic Marketing, 36, 1–10.CrossRef Vargo, S. L., & Lusch, R. F. (2007). Service-dominant logic: Continuing the evolution. Journal of Academic Marketing, 36, 1–10.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Vargo, S. L., & Lusch, R. F. (2017). Service-dominant logic 2025. International Journal of Research in Marketing, 34(1), 46–67.CrossRef Vargo, S. L., & Lusch, R. F. (2017). Service-dominant logic 2025. International Journal of Research in Marketing, 34(1), 46–67.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Vargo, S. L., Maglio, P. P., & Akaka, M. A. (2008). On value and value co-creation: A service systems and service logic perspective. European Management Journal, 26, 145–152.CrossRef Vargo, S. L., Maglio, P. P., & Akaka, M. A. (2008). On value and value co-creation: A service systems and service logic perspective. European Management Journal, 26, 145–152.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Vygotsky, L. S. (1986). Thought and language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Original work published 1934) Vygotsky, L. S. (1986). Thought and language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. (Original work published 1934)
Zurück zum Zitat Weber, M. (2006). Whitehead’s Pancreativism, Ontos/Verlad, Frankfurt. Weber, M. (2006). Whitehead’s Pancreativism, Ontos/Verlad, Frankfurt.
Zurück zum Zitat Weibel, A., & Six, F. (2013). Trust and control: The role of intrinsic motivation. In Handbook of advances in trust research. Edward Elgar Publishing. Weibel, A., & Six, F. (2013). Trust and control: The role of intrinsic motivation. In Handbook of advances in trust research. Edward Elgar Publishing.
Zurück zum Zitat Wertsch, J.V., del Rio, P., & Alvarez, A. (1995). Socio-cultural studies: history, action and mediation, in Wertsch JV, del Rio P and Alvarez A, Socio-cultural studies of the mind, CUP, Cambridge. Wertsch, J.V., del Rio, P., & Alvarez, A. (1995). Socio-cultural studies: history, action and mediation, in Wertsch JV, del Rio P and Alvarez A, Socio-cultural studies of the mind, CUP, Cambridge.
Zurück zum Zitat Whitehead, A.N. (1929) (1978). Process and reality: An essay in Cosmology, Free Press, NY. Whitehead, A.N. (1929) (1978). Process and reality: An essay in Cosmology, Free Press, NY.
Zurück zum Zitat Wittgenstein, L. (2001) (1923). Anscombe GEM translation, Philosophical Investigations, OUP, Oxford. Wittgenstein, L. (2001) (1923). Anscombe GEM translation, Philosophical Investigations, OUP, Oxford.
Zurück zum Zitat Zacka, B. (2017). When the state meets the street. Harvard University Press.CrossRef Zacka, B. (2017). When the state meets the street. Harvard University Press.CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Zucker, L. G. (1983). Organizations as Institutions. Research in the Sociology of Organizations, 2, 1–47. Zucker, L. G. (1983). Organizations as Institutions. Research in the Sociology of Organizations, 2, 1–47.
Metadaten
Titel
Logics and Agency in Public Management Research
verfasst von
Tony Kinder
Jari Stenvall
Antti Talonen
Publikationsdatum
27.09.2022
Verlag
Springer US
Erschienen in
Public Organization Review / Ausgabe 1/2023
Print ISSN: 1566-7170
Elektronische ISSN: 1573-7098
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11115-021-00576-8

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 1/2023

Public Organization Review 1/2023 Zur Ausgabe

Premium Partner