Skip to main content
Erschienen in: Social Choice and Welfare 1/2014

01.01.2014 | Original Contribution

How frequently do different voting rules encounter voting paradoxes in three-candidate elections?

verfasst von: Florenz Plassmann, T. Nicolaus Tideman

Erschienen in: Social Choice and Welfare | Ausgabe 1/2014

Einloggen

Aktivieren Sie unsere intelligente Suche, um passende Fachinhalte oder Patente zu finden.

search-config
loading …

Abstract

We estimate the frequencies with which ten voting anomalies (ties and nine voting paradoxes) occur under 14 voting rules, using a statistical model that simulates voting situations that follow the same distribution as voting situations in actual elections. Thus the frequencies that we estimate from our simulated data are likely to be very close to the frequencies that would be observed in actual three-candidate elections. We find that two Condorcet-consistent voting rules do, the Black rule and the Nanson rule, encounter most paradoxes and ties less frequently than the other rules do, especially in elections with few voters. The Bucklin rule, the Plurality rule, and the Anti-plurality rule tend to perform worse than the other eleven rules, especially when the number of voters becomes large.

Sie haben noch keine Lizenz? Dann Informieren Sie sich jetzt über unsere Produkte:

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft+Technik" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 102.000 Bücher
  • über 537 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Automobil + Motoren
  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Elektrotechnik + Elektronik
  • Energie + Nachhaltigkeit
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Maschinenbau + Werkstoffe
  • Versicherung + Risiko

Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Springer Professional "Wirtschaft"

Online-Abonnement

Mit Springer Professional "Wirtschaft" erhalten Sie Zugriff auf:

  • über 67.000 Bücher
  • über 340 Zeitschriften

aus folgenden Fachgebieten:

  • Bauwesen + Immobilien
  • Business IT + Informatik
  • Finance + Banking
  • Management + Führung
  • Marketing + Vertrieb
  • Versicherung + Risiko




Jetzt Wissensvorsprung sichern!

Anhänge
Nur mit Berechtigung zugänglich
Fußnoten
1
See, for example, Merrill (1984), Chamberlin and Featherston (1986), Nurmi (1992, 1999), Stern (1993), and Tideman and Plassmann (2012).
 
2
For example, Gehrlein (2006, p. 104) writes: “[N]one of the studies referenced above have ever suggested that IAC, IC, DC or UC reflect reality in any particular situation” where IAC, IC, DC, and UC refer to models of vote-casting outcomes used in the vast majority of previous studies.
 
3
The spatial model can be viewed either as a model of voter behavior that explains why voters submit specific rankings or as a model of vote-casting outcomes with which to simulate voting situations. Previous research has focused on the spatial model as a model of voter behavior. In contrast, we use the spatial model only because of its ability to simulate voting situations with the same distribution as observed voting situations, not because we want to defend it as a model of voter behavior.
 
4
See Tideman (2006, pp. 57–74) for details.
 
5
Approval Voting was listed on only 15 of the 22 ballots. However, Approval Voting received 5 more votes than the voting rule with the second-most votes: the Alternative Vote. It is notable that, unlike the question of who should be mayor, the question of which voting rules deserve further study is inherently a question that invites a plural answer and is therefore more likely to be regarded as answered suitably through Approval Voting.
 
6
Nurmi (1999, p. 120) also classifies voting paradoxes into four categories. His and our first two categories are the same, but his and our last two categories are different.
 
7
In contrast, a weak Condorcet winner is a candidate who is not beaten by any other candidates in pairwise comparison, using majority rule.
 
8
For example, Felsenthal (2012, p. 33) writes: “Although assessing the severity of the various paradoxes is largely a subjective matter, there seems to be a wide consensus that a voting procedure which is susceptible to an especially serious paradox ... i.e., a voting procedure which may elect a pareto-dominated candidate, or elect a Condorcet (and absolute) loser, or display lack of monotonicity, or not elect an absolute winner, should be disqualified as a reasonable voting procedure regardless of the probability that these paradoxes may occur.” Felsenthal (2012, p. 21) writes: “...we hold that a Condorcet winner, if one exists, ought always to be elected.”
 
9
See, for example, Fishburn (1974a) and Saari (2001).
 
10
Suppose that a weak monotonicity paradox occurs when three voters change their ballots. Then consider the voting situation after two of those changes have been made. This voting situation provides an instance of the strong version of the paradox because the paradox occurs when the third voter changes his ballot. However, we should expect to observe occurrences of the weak versions of the monotonicity paradoxes more frequently than occurrences of the strong versions, because a weak version occurs every time when the strong version occurs, but not vice versa.
 
11
Some voting rules—for example, the Kemeny rule and the Coombs rule (see Sect. 3.2)—ignore information from ballots with a single candidate.
 
12
Consider an election with 11 voters and three candidates, \(A,\,B\), and \(C\), and voting situation ABC (3), ACB (2), CAB (3), CBA (1), BCA (2), and BAC (0). Candidate \(C\) wins under the Nanson rule (see Sect. 3.2). Candidate \(C\) still wins if one of the two voters with ranking ACB truncates his ballot, which we record as 3.5 votes for ABC and 1.5 votes for ACB. If the other voter also truncates his ballot so that there are 4 votes for ABC and 1 vote for ACB, then the Nanson rule declares \(A\) the winner. If the starting voting situation can contain only integers (that is, if we cannot start with truncated ballots), then this example describes a violation of the weak truncation paradox but not of the strong truncation paradox.
 
13
With our exclusion of truncated ballots from the election results that we simulate, we find that the Nanson rule does not encounter the strong truncation paradox at all, while the Copeland rule and the Alternative Schwartz rule do not encounter the strong truncation paradox when the number of voters is odd. However, all three rules encounter the weak truncation paradox for even and odd numbers of voters.
 
14
It would nevertheless be in the spirit by which other anomalies are labeled as voting paradoxes to count a tie as a “paradox.” One purpose of voting is to determine a winning candidate, and the voting rule, “paradoxically,” fails to achieve that purpose when there is a tie. This is arguably as paradoxical as the situation in which a voting rule fails to elect a Condorcet winner. Another voting event in this category occurs when an electorate is committed to majority rule, but there are more than two candidates and no candidate receives a majority of the votes.
 
15
The Alternative Vote can be described as an application of the Single Transferable Vote to the situation in which only a single candidate is to be elected. The Single Transferable Vote was proposed independently by Carl George Andrae in 1855 and by Thomas Hare in 1857.
 
16
For example, for the ranking \(A > B >C\), count (1) the number of ballots on which \(A\) is ranked ahead of \(B\), (2) the number of ballots on which \(A\) is ranked ahead of \(C\), and (3) the number of ballots on which \(B\) is ranked ahead of \(C\). The score of the ranking \(A> B > C\) is determined as (1) + (2) + (3).
 
17
See Tideman (2006, Ch. 13) for descriptions of these voting rules.
 
18
Tideman (2006, p. 237), Felsenthal (2012), and Nurmi (2012) report similar tables that include additional voting rules and additional paradoxes, and they provide proofs for the vulnerability of each voting rule to the paradoxes in Table 1. Nurmi (1999) establishes the vulnerability of various voting rules to different paradoxes without summarizing his results in a table. These three authors also provide examples of the vulnerability of each rule to the paradoxes listed in Table 1. Tideman (2006, Ch. 13) provides explanations for why different rules are not vulnerable to certain paradoxes.
Table 1
Vulnerability of voting rules to different paradoxes and to ties in elections with three candidates, as observed in our 16,000,000 simulated elections
 
Condorcet winner paradox
Borda’s paradox
Absolute majority paradox
Absolute loser paradox
Lack of monotonicity paradox
Truncation paradox
No-show paradox
Reinforcement paradox
Violations of the SCC condition
Ties
 
(1)
(2)
(3)
(4)
(5)
(6)
(7)
(8)
(9)
(10)
Alternative Vote
x
   
x
\(\bullet ^{1}\)
x
x
x
x
Anti-plurality
x
x
x
  
x
  
x
x
Borda
x
 
x
  
x
  
x
x
Bucklin
x
x
   
x
x
x
x
x
Coombs
x
   
x
x
x
x
x
x
Estimated Centrality
x
    
x
x
x
x
x
Plurality
x
x
 
x
    
x
x
Alternative Schwartz
     
x
x
x
x
x
Alternative Smith
     
x
x
x
x
x
Black
     
x
x
x
x
x
Copeland
     
x
x
x
x
x
Dodgson
 
\(\bullet ^{2}\)
  
\(\bullet ^{3}\)
x
\(\bullet ^{4}\)
x
x
x
Kemeny
     
x
\(\bullet ^{4}\)
x
x
x
Nanson
    
\(\bullet ^{5}\)
x
\(\bullet ^{4}\)
x
x
x
\(^{1}\)Nurmi (1999, p. 63) shows that the Alternative Vote is vulnerable to the truncation paradox in four-candidate elections
\(^{2}\)Fishburn (1977) shows that the Dodgson rule is vulnerable to Borda’s paradox in elections with seven candidates
\(^{3}\)Fishburn (1982) shows that the Dodgson rule is vulnerable to the lack of monotonicity paradox only in elections with more than three candidates
\(^{4}\)Nurmi (2012) shows that the Kemeny rule and the Nanson rule are vulnerable to the no-show paradox in four-candidate elections, and that the Dodgson rule is vulnerable to the no-show paradox in five-candidate elections
\(^{5}\)Felsenthal (2012) shows that the Nanson rule is vulnerable to the lack of monotonicity paradox in four-candidate elections
 
19
For each simulated election, we choose randomly one of the six strict rankings as a tie-breaking ranking, and we resolve all ties between any two candidates according to the order in which these candidates are listed in the tie-breaking ranking. This procedure ensures that for any given voting situation we resolve all ties that we encounter during the evaluation of our 14 voting rules in the same way.
 
20
For example, the August 19, 2012 edition of the White Lake Beacon of Whitehall, Michigan reports: “Two ties in the Aug. 7 primary election have been broken as a result of drawings at the Muskegon County Clerk’s office this morning.”
 
21
We determine the frequencies of the reinforcement paradox by sampling ballots for two separate elections, which we then combine to determine whether the paradox occurred for any voting rule. In contrast, we determine the frequencies of all other paradoxes from a single sample of ballots. There is no obvious way in which to divide the ballots from a single election into two distinct sets that would yield the appropriate distribution of rankings in the two new sets and would permit us to examine reinforcement. Similarly, we might not achieve the appropriate distribution of rankings if we routinely sample two separate sets of rankings that we then combine into a single set and which would permit us to examine the frequency of all anomalies besides reinforcement. However, the frequencies with which the reinforcement paradox occurs in elections with 20 and more voters (see Table 12) are so low that their omission has no more than a minor effect on the frequencies in Table 2.
Table 2
Frequency of elections in which at least one paradox and/or a tie occurs
 
Number of voters
 
10
20
50
100
1,000
10,000
100,000
1,000,000
Alternative Vote (%)
25.68
14.84
6.61
3.56
0.71
0.43
0.39
0.39
Anti-plurality (%)
45.42
33.28
23.00
18.73
14.28
13.86
13.80
13.82
Borda (%)
25.89
16.62
9.18
6.17
3.02
2.69
2.66
2.67
Bucklin (%)
30.87
23.22
16.79
14.08
11.17
10.93
10.88
10.88
Coombs (%)
25.12
14.84
6.63
3.55
0.69
0.40
0.36
0.36
Estimated Centrality (%)
27.87
15.31
8.26
5.11
2.06
1.68
1.63
1.65
Plurality (%)
29.24
20.58
12.37
8.81
5.06
4.60
4.59
4.58
Alternative Schwartz (%)
24.60
14.10
5.99
3.06
0.38
0.12
0.09
0.09
Alternative Smith (%)
24.60
14.10
5.99
3.06
0.38
0.12
0.09
0.09
Black (%)
24.60
14.10
5.99
3.06
0.38
0.12
0.09
0.09
Copeland (%)
24.60
14.10
5.99
3.06
0.38
0.12
0.09
0.09
Dodgson (%)
24.60
14.10
5.99
3.06
0.38
0.12
0.09
0.09
Kemeny (%)
24.60
14.10
5.99
3.06
0.38
0.12
0.09
0.09
Nanson (%)
24.60
14.10
5.99
3.06
0.38
0.12
0.09
0.09
 
Number of voters
 
11
21
51
101
1,001
10,001
100,001
1,000,001
Alternative Vote (%)
4.90
3.70
1.80
1.08
0.46
0.40
0.40
0.39
Anti-plurality (%)
34.47
27.27
20.46
17.41
14.18
13.83
13.86
13.82
Borda (%)
11.96
9.30
6.31
4.79
2.89
2.68
2.67
2.66
Bucklin (%)
13.61
14.27
13.27
12.34
11.04
10.91
10.93
10.90
Coombs (%)
4.47
3.58
1.82
1.08
0.43
0.37
0.36
0.35
Estimated Centrality (%)
8.72
7.33
4.96
3.72
1.93
1.68
1.57
1.64
Plurality (%)
18.81
13.98
9.66
7.58
4.92
4.62
4.55
4.56
Alternative Schwartz (%)
2.79
1.82
0.86
0.48
0.12
0.09
0.09
0.09
Alternative Smith (%)
3.79
2.36
1.04
0.55
0.12
0.09
0.09
0.09
Black (%)
6.00
3.36
1.28
0.62
0.12
0.09
0.09
0.09
Copeland (%)
2.79
1.82
0.86
0.48
0.12
0.09
0.09
0.09
Dodgson (%)
2.79
1.82
0.86
0.48
0.12
0.09
0.09
0.09
Kemeny (%)
2.79
1.82
0.86
0.48
0.12
0.09
0.09
0.09
Nanson (%)
2.79
1.82
0.86
0.48
0.12
0.09
0.09
0.09
 
22
For example, Article 1 of the US Constitution specifies that, in his function as president of the US Senate, the Vice President of the United States does not vote, except to break a tie.
Table 3
Frequency of ties
 
Number of voters
 
10
20
50
100
1,000
10,000
100,000
1,000,000
Alternative Vote (%)
21.00
11.52
4.94
2.52
0.25
0.03
0.00
0.00
Anti-plurality (%)
20.17
10.13
4.62
2.48
0.26
0.02
0.00
0.00
Borda (%)
7.61
4.27
1.83
0.93
0.09
0.01
0.00
0
Bucklin (%)
12.08
6.13
3.08
1.74
0.19
0.02
0.00
0.00
Coombs (%)
18.78
11.39
4.92
2.49
0.25
0.03
0.00
0.00
Estimated Centrality (%)
0.35
0.05
0.01
0.00
0
0
0
0
Plurality (%)
11.52
7.61
3.06
1.44
0.14
0.01
0.00
0.00
Alternative Schwartz (%)
20.56
11.33
4.78
2.43
0.25
0.03
0.00
0.00
Alternative Smith (%)
21.25
11.85
5.03
2.54
0.26
0.03
0.00
0.00
Black (%)
6.48
2.71
0.70
0.23
0.00
0.00
0
0
Copeland (%)
15.06
9.94
4.85
2.64
0.36
0.11
0.09
0.09
Dodgson (%)
15.05
9.80
4.62
2.43
0.26
0.03
0.00
0.00
Kemeny (%)
20.81
11.69
4.95
2.51
0.26
0.03
0.00
0.00
Nanson (%)
14.88
9.51
4.45
2.34
0.25
0.03
0.00
0.00
 
Number of voters
 
11
21
51
101
1,001
10,001
100,001
1,000,001
Alternative Vote (%)
1.05
1.18
0.34
0.10
0.01
0.00
0
0
Anti-plurality (%)
15.91
9.73
4.48
2.43
0.27
0.03
0.00
0.00
Borda (%)
7.01
4.07
1.77
0.90
0.09
0.01
0.00
0
Bucklin (%)
6.23
4.92
2.79
1.65
0.20
0.02
0.00
0.00
Coombs (%)
1.50
0.98
0.32
0.13
0.01
0.00
0.00
0
Estimated Centrality (%)
0.04
0.00
0
0.00
0
0
0
0
Plurality (%)
13.10
6.32
2.82
1.47
0.14
0.01
0.00
0.00
Alternative Schwartz (%)
0.35
0.23
0.06
0.02
0.00
0.00
0
0
Alternative Smith (%)
0.35
0.23
0.06
0.02
0.00
0.00
0
0
Black (%)
0.85
0.35
0.10
0.04
0.00
0.00
0
0
Copeland (%)
2.79
1.82
0.86
0.48
0.12
0.09
0.09
0.09
Dodgson\({}^\mathrm{a} (\%)\)
2.27
1.12
0.33
0.12
0.01
0.00
0.00
0
Kemeny\({}^\mathrm{a} (\%)\)
2.27
1.12
0.33
0.12
0.01
0.00
0.00
0
Nanson (%)
0.78
0.23
0.04
0.01
0
0
0
0
\({}^{\mathrm{a}}\) When the number of voters is odd, the Dodgson rule and the Kemeny rule always encounter ties in the same elections.
 
23
For example, the 12th Amendment to the United States Constitution specifies that, if the Electoral College does not reach a majority decision (which may happen because of a tie) to elect the president of the United States, then “from the persons having the highest numbers not exceeding three on the list of those voted for as President, the House of Representatives shall choose immediately, by ballot, the President.”
 
24
For example, in elections for the French National Assembly in which no candidate receives a majority of the votes in the first round, each member of the electorate is asked to cast a vote for one of the candidates who received at least 12.5 % of the votes, and the winner is the candidate who receives a plurality of the votes.
 
25
For example, rather than declaring a mistrial, judges often send deadlocked juries back to the jury room for further deliberations.
 
26
One could also resolve the tie by assessing the Copeland scores [which are 0 \((A)\), 1 \((B)\), and -1 \((C)\)], the Dodgson scores [which are 2 \((A)\), 1 \((B)\), and 6 \((C)\)], or the Kemeny scores of the six rankings [which are 84 (ABC), 84 (ACB), 64 (CAB), 66 (CBA), 66 (BCA) and 86 (BAC)]. Candidate \(B\) would win the election in each case.
 
27
Avoiding ties by using a different voting rule is equivalent to the common solution to the “anomaly” that there might be no majority winner when an attempt is made to use majority rule to elect a winner from more than two candidates. Thus in elections with more than two candidates, most people advocate replacing majority rule with a different rule.
 
28
The Copeland rule encounters a tie whenever there is a voting cycle, and the spatial model of vote-casting outcomes implies that the frequency of voting cycles converges to about 0.085 % as the number of voters becomes large (see Plassmann and Tideman 2011).
 
29
This occurs most notably for the Anti-plurality rule and the Bucklin rule.
 
30
In elections with odd numbers of voters, the Bucklin rule is vulnerable to the weak version but not the strong version of the no-show paradox. In our simulations, all occurrences of the weak no-show paradox for the Bucklin rule involve the emergence of a strict majority rule winner when one or more voters do not vote. Because a strict majority rule winner can emerge only when the number of voters is reduced from an even to an odd number, the strong no-show paradox can occur only in elections with even numbers of voters. As an example, consider an election with 31 voters and voting situation ABC (10), ACB (5), CAB (4), CBA (5), BCA (4), and BAC (3). No candidate wins a majority of the votes (16), and candidates \(A\) and \(B\) are tied with equal Bucklin scores of 22. Candidate \(A\) will win outright with a strict majority of 15 votes if two of the voters with ranking CAB do not vote, because their abstentions reduce the number of voters to 29. The weak no-show paradox occurs because by abstaining these two voters can ensure a victory of their preferred candidate \(A\), instead of a tie. However, if only one voter with ranking CAB does not vote, then \(A\)’s 15 first-place votes are not sufficient to win a strict majority of the votes (16); instead \(A\)’s Bucklin score falls to 21 and \(B\) wins the election. Although the strong no-show paradox will occur when this voting situation is the starting situation and another voter with ranking CAB does not vote, the starting number of voters (30) is even in this case.
 
31
We can approximate the standard errors of estimate as follows: for 10,000 Bernoulli trials, the standard error of estimate of the probability of success \(p\) is \(\sqrt{p(1-p)}/100\), so it is 0.5 % when the probability is 50 %, 0.3 % when the probability is 10 %, and 0.1 % when the probability is 1 %. Thus, for example, for elections with 100 voters, the standard error of the Copeland rule is about 0.06 % given the frequency of 3.50 % with which the weak truncation paradox occurs.
 
32
Merrill (1984) also reports results from five-candidate elections simulated with a spatial model that was not calibrated to actual voting situations; Chamberlin and Cohen (1978) report results from a similar model with four candidates. Chamberlin and Featherston (1986) report results from four-candidate elections simulated with a model similar to IC but whose probabilities, constant across elections, for the six rankings differ from 1/6 and that were calibrated to observed voting situations from five presidential elections of the American Psychological Association. None of these results are directly comparable with ours because they apply to elections with more than three candidates.
 
33
Calibrating the spatial model to voting situations with four candidates requires numerical integration of non-central triangular wedges of a trivariate normal distribution, and we have not yet developed an algorithm to accomplish this task.
 
34
Owing to the difficulty of having to integrate wedges underneath multivariate normal distributions, we can currently evaluate the spatial model only for elections with three candidates which requires the (relative straightforward) integration of wedges underneath a bivariate normal distribution.
 
35
To match the variance of the angles that we determine from observed election data, we parameterize the Dirichlet distribution so that each of the three shares is multiplied by the common constant 73.5008. Dividing the three values in the text by this number yields three shares that sum to 1.
 
36
For example, if candidate \(A\) is the winner of voting situation \(R\), then the four pairs of rankings are (ABC, BAC), (ACB, CAB), (BAC, BCA), (CAB, CBA).
 
37
In three-candidate elections in which voters must submit full rankings, we treat a truncated ballot for candidate \(X\) as half a ballot for each of the two rankings with \(X \)first. This treatment permits us to examine truncated rankings with two rules, the Kemeny rule and the Coombs rule, that do not permit ballots listing only a single candidate.
 
38
The definition of SCC requires that the winner for \(R\) be the unique winner.
 
Literatur
Zurück zum Zitat Arrow K (1951) Social choice and individual values, 1st edn. New York (2nd edn., New Haven, 1963) Arrow K (1951) Social choice and individual values, 1st edn. New York (2nd edn., New Haven, 1963)
Zurück zum Zitat Black D (1958) The theory of committees and elections. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Black D (1958) The theory of committees and elections. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Zurück zum Zitat Brams SJ (1982) The AMS nominating system is vulnerable to truncation of preferences. Not Am Math Soc 29:136–138 Brams SJ (1982) The AMS nominating system is vulnerable to truncation of preferences. Not Am Math Soc 29:136–138
Zurück zum Zitat Chamberlin JR, Cohen M (1978) Toward applicable social choice theory: a comparison of social choice functions under spatial model assumptions. Am Polit Sci Rev 72:1341–1356CrossRef Chamberlin JR, Cohen M (1978) Toward applicable social choice theory: a comparison of social choice functions under spatial model assumptions. Am Polit Sci Rev 72:1341–1356CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Chamberlin JR, Featherston F (1986) Selecting a voting system. J Polit 48(2):347–369CrossRef Chamberlin JR, Featherston F (1986) Selecting a voting system. J Polit 48(2):347–369CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Condorcet MJAN (1785) “Essai sur l’application de l’analyse à la probabilité des décisions rendues à la pluralité des voix”. L’Imprimerie Royale, Paris Condorcet MJAN (1785) “Essai sur l’application de l’analyse à la probabilité des décisions rendues à la pluralité des voix”. L’Imprimerie Royale, Paris
Zurück zum Zitat Coombs CH (1964) A theory of data. Wiley, New York Coombs CH (1964) A theory of data. Wiley, New York
Zurück zum Zitat Copeland AH (1951) A ‘reasonable’ social welfare function”. Mimeo, University of Michigan, Department of Mathematics, Seminar on Applications of Mathematics to the Social Sciences Copeland AH (1951) A ‘reasonable’ social welfare function”. Mimeo, University of Michigan, Department of Mathematics, Seminar on Applications of Mathematics to the Social Sciences
Zurück zum Zitat de Borda J-C (1784) Mémoire sur les élections au scrutin”. Histoire de l’Academie Royale des Sciences, Paris de Borda J-C (1784) Mémoire sur les élections au scrutin”. Histoire de l’Academie Royale des Sciences, Paris
Zurück zum Zitat Felsenthal DS (2012) Review of paradoxes afflicting procedures for electing a single candidate. In: Felsenthal DS, Machover M (eds) Electoral systems: paradoxes, assumptions, and procedures. Springer, Berlin, pp 19–91CrossRef Felsenthal DS (2012) Review of paradoxes afflicting procedures for electing a single candidate. In: Felsenthal DS, Machover M (eds) Electoral systems: paradoxes, assumptions, and procedures. Springer, Berlin, pp 19–91CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Fishburn PC (1974a) Paradoxes of voting. Am Polit Sci Rev 68:537–546CrossRef Fishburn PC (1974a) Paradoxes of voting. Am Polit Sci Rev 68:537–546CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Fishburn PC (1974b) On the sum-of-ranks winner when losers are removed. Discret Math 8:25–30 Fishburn PC (1974b) On the sum-of-ranks winner when losers are removed. Discret Math 8:25–30
Zurück zum Zitat Fishburn PC (1977) Condorcet social choice functions. SIAM J Appl Math 33:469–489CrossRef Fishburn PC (1977) Condorcet social choice functions. SIAM J Appl Math 33:469–489CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Fishburn PC (1982) Monotonicity paradoxes in the theory of elections. Discret Appl Math 4:119–134CrossRef Fishburn PC (1982) Monotonicity paradoxes in the theory of elections. Discret Appl Math 4:119–134CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Fishburn PC, Brams SJ (1983) Paradoxes of preferential voting. Math Mag 56:207–214CrossRef Fishburn PC, Brams SJ (1983) Paradoxes of preferential voting. Math Mag 56:207–214CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Gehrlein W (2006) Condorcet’s paradox. Springer, Berlin Gehrlein W (2006) Condorcet’s paradox. Springer, Berlin
Zurück zum Zitat Gehrlein W, Lepelley D (2011) Voting paradoxes and group coherence: the Condorcet efficiency of voting rules. Springer, BerlinCrossRef Gehrlein W, Lepelley D (2011) Voting paradoxes and group coherence: the Condorcet efficiency of voting rules. Springer, BerlinCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Good IJ, Tideman TN (1976) From individual to collective ordering through multidimensional attribute space. Proc R Soc Lond Ser A 347:371–385 Good IJ, Tideman TN (1976) From individual to collective ordering through multidimensional attribute space. Proc R Soc Lond Ser A 347:371–385
Zurück zum Zitat Hoag CG, Hallett GH (1926) Proportional representation. Macmillan, New York Hoag CG, Hallett GH (1926) Proportional representation. Macmillan, New York
Zurück zum Zitat Kemeny J (1959) Mathematics without numbers. Daedalus 88:577–591 Kemeny J (1959) Mathematics without numbers. Daedalus 88:577–591
Zurück zum Zitat Laslier J-F (2011) Lessons from in situ tests during French elections. In: Dolez B, Grofman B, Laurent A (eds) In situ and laboratory experiments on electoral law reform: French presidential elections. Springer, Heidelberg, pp 90–104 Laslier J-F (2011) Lessons from in situ tests during French elections. In: Dolez B, Grofman B, Laurent A (eds) In situ and laboratory experiments on electoral law reform: French presidential elections. Springer, Heidelberg, pp 90–104
Zurück zum Zitat Laslier J-F (2012) And the loser is plurality voting. In: Felsenthal DS, Machover M (eds) Electoral systems: paradoxes, assumptions, and procedures. Springer, Berlin, pp 327–351 Laslier J-F (2012) And the loser is plurality voting. In: Felsenthal DS, Machover M (eds) Electoral systems: paradoxes, assumptions, and procedures. Springer, Berlin, pp 327–351
Zurück zum Zitat Lepelley D, Merlin V (2001) Scoring run-off paradoxes for variable electo-rates. Econ Theory 17:53–80CrossRef Lepelley D, Merlin V (2001) Scoring run-off paradoxes for variable electo-rates. Econ Theory 17:53–80CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Merrill S (1984) A comparison of efficiency of multicandidate electoral systems. Am J Polit Sci 28:23–48CrossRef Merrill S (1984) A comparison of efficiency of multicandidate electoral systems. Am J Polit Sci 28:23–48CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Nanson E (1883) Methods of elections. Trans Proc R Soc Vic 19:197–240 Nanson E (1883) Methods of elections. Trans Proc R Soc Vic 19:197–240
Zurück zum Zitat Nurmi H (1992) An assessment of voting system simulations. Public Choice 73:459–487CrossRef Nurmi H (1992) An assessment of voting system simulations. Public Choice 73:459–487CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Nurmi H (1999) Voting paradoxes and how to deal with them. Springer, BerlinCrossRef Nurmi H (1999) Voting paradoxes and how to deal with them. Springer, BerlinCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Nurmi H (2012) On the relevance of theoretical results to voting system choice. In: Felsenthal DS, Machover M (eds) Electoral systems: paradoxes, assumptions, and procedures. Springer, Berlin, pp 255–274CrossRef Nurmi H (2012) On the relevance of theoretical results to voting system choice. In: Felsenthal DS, Machover M (eds) Electoral systems: paradoxes, assumptions, and procedures. Springer, Berlin, pp 255–274CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Saari DG (2001) Decisions and elections; explaining the unexpected. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeCrossRef Saari DG (2001) Decisions and elections; explaining the unexpected. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeCrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Smith JH (1973) Aggregation of preferences with variable electorate. Econometrica 41:1027–1041CrossRef Smith JH (1973) Aggregation of preferences with variable electorate. Econometrica 41:1027–1041CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Stern H (1993) Probability models on rankings and the electoral process. In: Flieger M, Verducci JS (eds) Probability models and statistical analysis for ranking data. Springer, Berlin, pp 173–195 Stern H (1993) Probability models on rankings and the electoral process. In: Flieger M, Verducci JS (eds) Probability models and statistical analysis for ranking data. Springer, Berlin, pp 173–195
Zurück zum Zitat Tideman TN (2006) Collective decisions and voting. Ashgate, Burlington Tideman TN (2006) Collective decisions and voting. Ashgate, Burlington
Zurück zum Zitat Tideman TN, Plassmann F (2012) Modeling the outcomes of vote-casting in actual elections. In: Felsenthal DS, Machover M (eds) Electoral systems: paradoxes, assumptions, and procedures. Springer, Berlin, pp 217–251 Tideman TN, Plassmann F (2012) Modeling the outcomes of vote-casting in actual elections. In: Felsenthal DS, Machover M (eds) Electoral systems: paradoxes, assumptions, and procedures. Springer, Berlin, pp 217–251
Zurück zum Zitat Young P (1974) An axiomatization of Borda’s rule. J Econ Theory 9:43–52CrossRef Young P (1974) An axiomatization of Borda’s rule. J Econ Theory 9:43–52CrossRef
Zurück zum Zitat Young P (1988) condorcet’s theory of voting. Am Pol Sci Rev 82: 1231–1244 Young P (1988) condorcet’s theory of voting. Am Pol Sci Rev 82: 1231–1244
Metadaten
Titel
How frequently do different voting rules encounter voting paradoxes in three-candidate elections?
verfasst von
Florenz Plassmann
T. Nicolaus Tideman
Publikationsdatum
01.01.2014
Verlag
Springer Berlin Heidelberg
Erschienen in
Social Choice and Welfare / Ausgabe 1/2014
Print ISSN: 0176-1714
Elektronische ISSN: 1432-217X
DOI
https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-013-0720-8

Weitere Artikel der Ausgabe 1/2014

Social Choice and Welfare 1/2014 Zur Ausgabe